![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
New Zealand Law Students Journal |
Last Updated: 17 November 2012
THE LAW OF EVIDENCE AND THE RULE OF LAW:
IS JUDICIAL DISCRETION CONSISTENT WITH THE RULE OF LAW?
ZOË PREBBLE*
Introduction
The rule of law is a notoriously difficult concept to define. Yet
to discuss any concept, it is necessary first to have
at least a broad idea of
what it means. This paper begins by proposing a working definition of the rule
of law so that a discussion
of the rule of law and its implications
for evidence law is possible. It then considers the distinction
between
rules and standards and in particular, whether or not the presence
of standards and discretion in our legal system, in
addition to rules, is
consistent with the rule of law.
The law of evidence contains a great deal of judicial discretion and for this
reason is a very useful lens through which to examine
rules and standards and
consider their respective rule of law implications. This paper discusses
four evidence law case-studies.
These are examined with particular
reference to predictability, a very important rule of law value, but the paper
also considers
other equally important rule of law values such as procedural due
process and fairness.
The paper notes that evidence law is procedural, as opposed to
substantive, in nature. This and other characteristics
of evidence law might
suggest at first glance that this area of law is a special case with respect to
rule of law values. However,
the paper argues that on closer consideration it is
clear that while evidence law is an especially striking case from a rule of law
perspective, it is not an exceptional or special case. Evidence law may
highlight certain rule of law issues rather dramatically,
but these same issues
also arise in other areas of law.
The paper concludes that the rule of law can indeed accommodate
standards and discretion. The rule of law, so defined,
is a complex
concept; but it is preferable to a narrow “rules only” definition in
both theoretical and pragmatic terms.
* BA (Hons) LLB (Hons), Victoria University of
Wellington.
88 The New Zealand Law Students’ Journal (2006) 1 NZLSJ
88 The New Zealand Law Students’ Journal (2006) 1
NZLSJ
A: The Rule of Law
1. A Working Definition of the Rule of Law
The rule of law is a complex concept. At a basic level, it expresses the idea that everyone is subject to the law and should obey it.1
Governments, as well as ordinary people, should be bound by the law.
Furthermore, Governments should only rule according to the law.
The rule of law
is a procedural constraint which prevents, or is inconsistent with, arbitrary
rule.2 It concerns the relationships between parts of government,
and between a government and its people. It is thus of significant
constitutional
importance.
However, attempts to provide a more detailed exposition of the
concept of the rule of law meet with difficulties. Many
features and
underlying values might be attributed to the concept. There exist
numerous permutations and combinations
of these features and values, and no
single collection of features and values is clearly identifiable as correct. The
rule of law
is “an essentially contested concept”.3
Still, the term is not so uncertain as to be meaningless. Its edges are
vague, but within these blurry parameters there are some
firm elements that most
commentators could agree upon. For present purposes, it will be useful to
propose a working definition
comprising such firm elements. A perfect
definition is certainly beyond the scope of this paper, but a working,
if
incomplete, definition will allow a discussion of the laws of evidence from a
broad rule of law standpoint.
A significant aspect of the working definition proposed by this paper is that the rule of law requires rule by, under, or through, law, as opposed
A: The Rule of Law
1. A Working Definition of the Rule of Law
The rule of law is a complex concept. At a basic level, it expresses the
idea that everyone is subject to the law
and should obey
it.1
Governments, as well as ordinary people, should be bound by
the law. Furthermore, Governments should only rule according to the law.
The
rule of law is a procedural constraint which prevents, or is inconsistent with,
arbitrary rule.2 It concerns the relationships between parts of
government, and between a government and its people. It is thus of
significant constitutional
importance.
However, attempts to provide a
more detailed exposition of the concept of the rule of law meet with
difficulties. Many
features and underlying values might be attributed to
the concept. There exist numerous permutations and combinations of
these
features and values, and no single collection of features and values is clearly
identifiable as correct. The rule of law is
“an essentially contested
concept”.3 Still, the term is not so uncertain as to be
meaningless. Its edges are vague, but within these blurry parameters there are
some
firm elements that most commentators could agree upon. For present
purposes, it will be useful to propose a working definition
comprising
such firm elements. A perfect definition is certainly beyond the scope
of this paper, but a working, if
incomplete, definition will allow a
discussion of the laws of evidence from a broad rule of law standpoint.
A
significant aspect of the working definition proposed by this paper is that the
rule of law requires rule by, under, or through,
law, as opposed
1 TRS Allan, “Rule of Law (Rechtsstaat)” in Edward Craig (ed) The Routledge Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Routledge, London, 1998) vol 8, p. 388.
2 See for instance FA Hayek The Constitution of Liberty, (Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1960); AV Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (Liberty Fund, Indianapolis, 1982). See also Allan, supra, n. 1, p. 388.
3 See for instance Jeremy Waldron “Is the Rule of Law an Essentially Contested Concept
(in Florida)?” (2002) Law and Philosophy 137; Rt Hon Sir Geoffrey Palmer “The New Zealand Constitution in 2005” in Jack Hodder, Geoffrey Palmer and ILM Richardson New Zealand’s Constitutional Arrangements: Where Are We Heading? (New Zealand Law Society, Wellington, p. 2005), para 39.
1 TRS Allan, “Rule of Law (Rechtsstaat)” in Edward
Craig (ed) The Routledge Encyclopedia of
Philosophy
(Routledge, London, 1998) vol 8, p. 388.
2 See for
instance FA Hayek The Constitution of Liberty, (Routledge & Kegan
Paul, London, 1960); AV Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the
Constitution (Liberty Fund, Indianapolis, 1982). See also Allan, supra, n.
1, p. 388.
3 See for instance Jeremy Waldron “Is the Rule of Law
an Essentially Contested Concept
(in Florida)?” (2002) Law and
Philosophy 137; Rt Hon Sir Geoffrey Palmer “The New Zealand Constitution
in 2005”
in Jack Hodder, Geoffrey Palmer and ILM Richardson New
Zealand’s Constitutional Arrangements: Where Are We Heading?
(New Zealand Law Society, Wellington, p. 2005), para
39.
Judicial Discretion and the Rule of Law in Evidence 89
to arbitrary or unconstrained forms of authority.4 It
also requires general laws; where law is too particular, there is a
risk of bias or unequal treatment. Furthermore,
the rule of law holds that
no person or body should be above the law and laws should be prospective and
promulgated since people
cannot plan their lives around secret or retrospective
laws .5
Procedural due process and natural justice are also key underlying
values, although arguably these terms themselves involve
a degree of
conceptual vagueness.6 Law provides an official means of settling
civil disputes and deciding criminal guilt. If it falls to the law to settle
these matters,
then the rule of law requires that the law must
provide analytically sound processes for carrying out this task.
Simply stated, the working definition adopted in this paper holds that the
rule of law is a general, impersonal, predictable
and analytically
sound brand of non-arbitrary governance.7
2. Rules, Standards and Judicial Discretion
Any aspects of the rule of law that are not assumed as part of the
working definition of the rule of law remain, for present
purposes, essentially
contested. One such detail not yet been addressed by the working
definition is the question of whether
or not the presence of flexible
principles, as opposed to rigid rules, is reconcilable with the rule of law.
This question is
of central importance to understanding the concept of the
rule of law. The remainder of this paper aims to address this question.
Rules and standards are often presented as mutually exclusive categories. Various generic qualities are often, apparently very plausibly, attributed to each of the two categories – in particular, rules seem hard
Judicial Discretion and the Rule of Law in Evidence 89
to
arbitrary or unconstrained forms of authority.4 It also
requires general laws; where law is too particular, there is a risk
of bias or unequal treatment. Furthermore,
the rule of law holds that no
person or body should be above the law and laws should be prospective and
promulgated since people
cannot plan their lives around secret or retrospective
laws .5
Procedural due process and natural justice are
also key underlying values, although arguably these terms themselves
involve
a degree of conceptual vagueness.6 Law provides an official
means of settling civil disputes and deciding criminal guilt. If it falls to the
law to settle these matters,
then the rule of law requires that the law
must provide analytically sound processes for carrying out this
task.
Simply stated, the working definition adopted in this paper holds
that the rule of law is a general, impersonal, predictable
and
analytically sound brand of non-arbitrary governance.7
2. Rules, Standards and Judicial Discretion
Any aspects of
the rule of law that are not assumed as part of the working definition of
the rule of law remain, for present
purposes, essentially contested. One such
detail not yet been addressed by the working definition is the question of
whether
or not the presence of flexible principles, as opposed to rigid rules,
is reconcilable with the rule of law. This question is
of central importance
to understanding the concept of the rule of law. The remainder of this paper
aims to address this question.
Rules and standards are often
presented as mutually exclusive categories. Various generic qualities are
often, apparently
very plausibly, attributed to each of the two categories
– in particular, rules seem hard
4 For instance Dicey, supra, n. 2, pp. 110-115; see also Antonin Scalia A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law: An Essay by Antonin Scalia With Commentary by Amy Gutman, Editor, et al (Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1997) pp. 17, 25.
5 Dicey, supra, n. 2, p. 114.
6 Bryan Garner A Black’s Law Dictionary (8th ed., West Publishing Co, St Paul, Minnesota,
2004), pp. 539 and 881.
7 Kent Greenawalt Law and Objectivity (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1992) p. 7.
4 For instance Dicey, supra, n. 2, pp. 110-115; see also
Antonin Scalia A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law: An
Essay by Antonin Scalia With Commentary by Amy Gutman, Editor, et al
(Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1997) pp. 17,
25.
5 Dicey, supra, n. 2, p. 114.
6 Bryan Garner A
Black’s Law Dictionary (8th ed., West Publishing Co, St Paul,
Minnesota,
2004), pp. 539 and 881.
7 Kent Greenawalt Law
and Objectivity (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1992) p.
7.
and fast while standards seem open-ended.8 It is often said of
rules that they tend to be rigid and logical in form. For instance, many rules
are of the structure “if
x then y”. Because of their
logical structure, it is credibly claimed of rules that they operate in a
very predictable
manner. That is, the necessary and sufficient conditions for
particular legal consequences are clearly laid out in advance
so that
individuals can easily forecast how and if a rule will apply to them. If it is
correct that rules are predictable, then
they allow individuals to make well
informed decisions about how to behave.9 It might also be plausibly
suggested that the rigid logical structure of rules also means that they can be
very easily and efficiently
applied by officials.10 An official can
merely plug the relevant facts into a formal rule and the rule itself
mechanically churns out the conclusion
or result; to decide a case according to
a rigid rule, an official need not exercise any discretion at all.
Rules, as
a category, are generally thought to be predictable and as a
generalisation at least, this seems credible. All the predictability
that might
reasonably be supposed to come with the use of rules rather than discretion
seems highly consistent with our rule
of law ideal. The position
regarding flexible standards is less clear.11
It is often plausibly said of standards that they leave a deal of discretion with the judge at the point of application.12 As a consequence, they are often thought to operate less predictably than rules. Potentially this could be a problem when viewed from a rule of law perspective: the exercise of discretion, if abused, looks like arbitrary rule; even if not abused, by dealing with cases individually, discretion can lead to inconsistencies and inequalities across a legal system.13 For these reasons, standards are often accused of being inconsistent with the rule of law.14
and fast while standards seem open-ended.8 It is often said of
rules that they tend to be rigid and logical in form. For instance, many rules
are of the structure “if
x then y”. Because of their
logical structure, it is credibly claimed of rules that they operate in a
very predictable
manner. That is, the necessary and sufficient conditions for
particular legal consequences are clearly laid out in advance
so that
individuals can easily forecast how and if a rule will apply to them. If it is
correct that rules are predictable, then
they allow individuals to make well
informed decisions about how to behave.9 It might also be plausibly
suggested that the rigid logical structure of rules also means that they can be
very easily and efficiently
applied by officials.10 An official can
merely plug the relevant facts into a formal rule and the rule itself
mechanically churns out the conclusion
or result; to decide a case according to
a rigid rule, an official need not exercise any discretion at all.
Rules, as
a category, are generally thought to be predictable and as a
generalisation at least, this seems credible. All the predictability
that might
reasonably be supposed to come with the use of rules rather than discretion
seems highly consistent with our rule
of law ideal. The position
regarding flexible standards is less clear.11
It is often
plausibly said of standards that they leave a deal of discretion with the judge
at the point of application.12 As a consequence, they are often
thought to operate less predictably than rules. Potentially this could
be a problem when
viewed from a rule of law perspective: the exercise of
discretion, if abused, looks like arbitrary rule; even if not abused,
by
dealing with cases individually, discretion can lead to inconsistencies and
inequalities across a legal system.13 For these reasons,
standards are often accused of being inconsistent with the rule of
law.14
8 Cass R Sunstein “Problems with Rules” (1995) 83 Cal L Rev 953, p. 959.
9 See Fred Schauer Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-
Making in Law and in Life (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1991), pp. 137–138.
10 Schauer, supra, n. 9, p. 147.
11 See generally Barry Hoffmaster “Understanding Judicial Discretion” (1982) 1
Law and Philosophy 21; Kenneth Henley “Abstract Principles, Mid-Level Principles, and
the Rule of Law” (1993) 12 Law and Philosophy 121.
12 Schauer, supra, n. 9, pp. 149–150; David P Leonard “Power and Responsibility in
Evidence Law” (1990) 63 S Cal L Rev 937, p. 937; but see Sunstein, supra, n. 8.
13 George C Christie “An Essay on Discretion” [1986] Duke LJ 747, p. 754.
14 For instance Antonin Scalia “The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules” (1989) 56 U Chi L Rev 1175.
8 Cass R Sunstein “Problems with Rules” (1995) 83 Cal
L Rev 953, p. 959.
9 See Fred Schauer Playing by the Rules: A
Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-
Making in Law
and in Life (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1991), pp. 137–138.
10
Schauer, supra, n. 9, p. 147.
11 See generally Barry
Hoffmaster “Understanding Judicial Discretion” (1982) 1
Law
and Philosophy 21; Kenneth Henley “Abstract Principles, Mid-Level
Principles, and
the Rule of Law” (1993) 12 Law and Philosophy
121.
12 Schauer, supra, n. 9, pp. 149–150; David P Leonard
“Power and Responsibility in
Evidence Law” (1990) 63 S Cal
L Rev 937, p. 937; but see Sunstein, supra, n. 8.
13 George C Christie
“An Essay on Discretion” [1986] Duke LJ 747, p.
754.
14 For instance Antonin Scalia “The Rule of Law
as a Law of Rules” (1989) 56 U Chi L Rev 1175.
The issue then is whether or not these accusations are correct such that
standards and discretion are antithetical to the
rule of law. To
determine this issue, we must first answer a prior question: what do we think
law is, or should be?15 If we decide that law is or
should be wholly rigid and predictable, then standards may fall short. Further,
even rules are unlikely
to meet this test. However, if we allow that
law can sometimes accommodate a degree of discretion, then standards as well
as
rules may be consistent with the rule of law after all.
3. Rules and Standards: Binary Terms?
Rules and standards are often viewed as polar opposites.16
However, they are perhaps better understood not as binary terms but points
on a continuum.17 It logically possible for a rule to be entirely
certain such that it decides every possible future scenario in
advance
– an omniscient legislator could draft rules detailed
enough to cover all possible eventualities. However,
in practice,
legislators are not omniscient and their rules can seldom be wholly
certain; to some degree, rules
are “open-textured”. Paradigm
cases will fall within a rule’s “core of certainty”, but
other
cases not contemplated at the time of drafting may occupy a “fringe
of vagueness”.18 As such, rules cannot wholly eliminate the
possibility of future discretion.19
Standards seem to be located further towards the “uncertain” or “flexible” extreme of the continuum than rules are.20 However, the judicial discretion associated with the application of standards still tends not to be untrammelled. Generally a judge does not have a wide discretion to make whatever decision he or she sees fit; the discretion is to decide only after having taken into account stipulated criteria or
The issue then is whether or not these accusations are correct such that
standards and discretion are antithetical to the
rule of law. To
determine this issue, we must first answer a prior question: what do we think
law is, or should be?15 If we decide that law is or
should be wholly rigid and predictable, then standards may fall short. Further,
even rules are unlikely
to meet this test. However, if we allow that
law can sometimes accommodate a degree of discretion, then standards as well
as
rules may be consistent with the rule of law after all.
3. Rules and Standards: Binary Terms?
Rules and standards are
often viewed as polar opposites.16 However, they are perhaps
better understood not as binary terms but points on a continuum.17
It logically possible for a rule to be entirely certain such that it
decides every possible future scenario in advance
– an
omniscient legislator could draft rules detailed enough to cover all
possible eventualities. However,
in practice, legislators are not
omniscient and their rules can seldom be wholly certain; to some
degree, rules
are “open-textured”. Paradigm cases will fall
within a rule’s “core of certainty”, but other
cases not
contemplated at the time of drafting may occupy a “fringe of
vagueness”.18 As such, rules cannot wholly eliminate the
possibility of future discretion.19
Standards seem to be
located further towards the “uncertain” or
“flexible” extreme of the continuum
than rules are.20
However, the judicial discretion associated with the application of
standards still tends not to be untrammelled. Generally
a judge does not
have a wide discretion to make whatever decision he or she sees fit;
the discretion is to decide only after having taken into account
stipulated criteria or
15 Cass R Sunstein “Rules and Rulelessness” (working paper, University of Chicago,
1994), p. 1; David P Leonard supra, n. 12, p. 939.
16 Sunstein, supra, n. 8, p. 961.
17 See Sunstein, supra, n. 15, p. 4; James G Wilson “Surveying the Forms of Doctrine on the Bright-Line Balancing Test Continuum” (1995) 27 Ariz St LJ 773.
18 HLA Hart The Concept of Law (Oxford University Press, London, 1961) pp. 119-120 and
125.
19 Hart, supra, n. 18, p. 124; Sunstein, supra, n. 15, p. 4.
20 Sunstein, supra, n. 8, p. 961.
15 Cass R Sunstein “Rules and Rulelessness”
(working paper, University of Chicago,
1994), p. 1; David P Leonard supra, n.
12, p. 939.
16 Sunstein, supra, n. 8, p. 961.
17
See Sunstein, supra, n. 15, p. 4; James G Wilson “Surveying the
Forms of Doctrine on the Bright-Line Balancing Test Continuum”
(1995) 27
Ariz St LJ 773.
18 HLA Hart The Concept of Law (Oxford
University Press, London, 1961) pp. 119-120 and
125.
19
Hart, supra, n. 18, p. 124; Sunstein, supra, n. 15, p. 4.
20
Sunstein, supra, n. 8, p. 961.
considerations.21 So, just as rules are not wholly certain,
standards are not wholly flexible.
4. Discretion and the Rule of Law
If rules and standards are not mutually exclusive, but to some degree
coextensive, then there is no prima facie reason to assume
that one is
consistent with the rule of law while the other is not. Since empirical
observation tells us that both rules and standards
involve discretion, the
practical and theoretical difference between the two turns out to be one of
degree rather than kind.
This observation can be interpreted in two ways, depending on how we choose
to refine our working definition of the rule of law. First,
we may focus on
risks of arbitrariness, bias and abuse that accompany the presence of
discretion and so conclude that the
presence of discretion violates our rule of
law ideal. According to this definition, the rule of law strictly requires rule
by or
through rules alone.
The second way to interpret the observation is to acknowledge the risks of uncertainty while also highlighting the merits of discretion and the risks of having only completely rigid rules. When applying strict rules there is a risk of ignoring relevant considerations that do not fit within the formal structure of a particular rule. Discretion allows flexibility and so abates this risk. Once the advantages of flexibility are acknowledged alongside the risks, it is clearly too simplistic to hold that discretion and standards are necessarily incompatible with the rule of law. Discretion may be compatible with the rule of law – the rule of law would just be a more complex concept than we might initially have thought.
The choice between these two definitions involves a trade-off between conceptual elegance and simplicity on the one hand, and practical relevance on the other. If we choose the first, stricter definition of the rule of law then it is fairly easy for us to understand the concept itself
considerations.21 So, just as rules are not wholly certain,
standards are not wholly flexible.
4. Discretion and the Rule of Law
If rules and standards are
not mutually exclusive, but to some degree coextensive, then there is no prima
facie reason to assume
that one is consistent with the rule of law while the
other is not. Since empirical observation tells us that both rules and standards
involve discretion, the practical and theoretical difference between the two
turns out to be one of degree rather than kind.
This observation can be
interpreted in two ways, depending on how we choose to refine our working
definition of the rule of law. First,
we may focus on risks of
arbitrariness, bias and abuse that accompany the presence of discretion
and so conclude that the
presence of discretion violates our rule of law ideal.
According to this definition, the rule of law strictly requires rule by or
through rules alone.
The second way to interpret the observation
is to acknowledge the risks of uncertainty while also highlighting the merits
of discretion
and the risks of having only completely rigid rules. When
applying strict rules there is a risk of ignoring relevant considerations
that
do not fit within the formal structure of a particular rule. Discretion allows
flexibility and so abates this risk. Once the
advantages of flexibility are
acknowledged alongside the risks, it is clearly too simplistic to hold that
discretion and standards
are necessarily incompatible with the rule of law.
Discretion may be compatible with the rule of law – the rule of law would
just be a more complex concept than we might initially have thought.
The
choice between these two definitions involves a trade-off between conceptual
elegance and simplicity on the one hand,
and practical relevance on the
other. If we choose the first, stricter definition of the rule of law then it is
fairly easy for
us to understand the concept itself
21 For more on discretion see: Maurice Rosenberg “Judicial Discretion of the Trial Court, Viewed from Above” (1971) 22 Syracuse L Rev 635; Christie, supra, n. 13, p. 747; Rosemary Pattenden The Judge, Discretion, and the Criminal Trial (Clarendon Press, Oxford,
1982), p. 3; KC Davis Discretionary Justice (Greenwood Press, Westport, 1969), p. 4; Thomas M Mengler “The Theory of Discretion in the Federal Rules of Evidence” (1989)
74 Iowa L Rev 413, p. 425; Ronald Dworkin “The Model of Rules” (1967) 35 U Chi L Rev 14, p. 32.
21 For more on discretion see: Maurice Rosenberg “Judicial
Discretion of the Trial Court, Viewed from Above” (1971) 22 Syracuse L Rev
635; Christie, supra, n. 13, p. 747; Rosemary Pattenden The Judge,
Discretion, and the Criminal Trial (Clarendon Press, Oxford,
1982), p. 3;
KC Davis Discretionary Justice (Greenwood Press, Westport, 1969), p. 4;
Thomas M Mengler “The Theory of Discretion in the Federal Rules of
Evidence”
(1989)
74 Iowa L Rev 413, p. 425; Ronald Dworkin “The
Model of Rules” (1967) 35 U Chi L Rev 14, p. 32.
and to test whether or not a particular legal system adheres to the rule of
law. The rule of law will be present in a legal system
only if that system
contains rules alone. The problem, however, is that the definition
is too narrow and idealised
to accommodate real legal systems. On the
other hand, if we prefer the second definition then legal systems containing
flexible principles as well as rigid rules may still have the rule of law
– it becomes a more difficult concept
to understand but it is
one which real legal systems actually have a chance to have.
B. Evidence Law and the Rule of Law: Discretion in Evidence Law
Evidence law is an area that is deeply infused with judicial discretion.22
This makes it a good lens through which to view the question of
whether or not constrained discretion can be consistent
with the rule of law.
This part of the paper will set out several case studies involving different
areas of evidence law. It
will then assess whether or not discretion
is consistent with the rule of law, both in the particular case of evidence law,
and in general terms.
1. Case Study One: Examples of Evidentiary Privilege
While evidence law involves a lot of judicial discretion,
certain evidentiary privileges serve as useful reminders
that evidence law is
not solely concerned with judicial discretion. An evidentiary privilege
is the right to refuse to disclose, or to allow another person
to
disclose, otherwise admissible, relevant evidence.23 That is,
privileged evidence may be withheld notwithstanding its usefulness.
Marital privilege is an example of a rule of evidence that does not require, or allow for, the exercise of judicial discretion. The statutory test for the availability of marital privilege sets out that it covers only communications between a husband and a wife during their married
and to test whether or not a particular legal system adheres to the rule of
law. The rule of law will be present in a legal system
only if that system
contains rules alone. The problem, however, is that the definition
is too narrow and idealised
to accommodate real legal systems. On the
other hand, if we prefer the second definition then legal systems containing
flexible principles as well as rigid rules may still have the rule of law
– it becomes a more difficult concept
to understand but it is
one which real legal systems actually have a chance to have.
B. Evidence Law and the Rule of Law: Discretion in Evidence Law
Evidence law is an area that is deeply infused with judicial
discretion.22
This makes it a good lens through which to
view the question of whether or not constrained discretion can be consistent
with the rule of law. This part of the paper will set out several case studies
involving different areas of evidence law. It
will then assess whether
or not discretion is consistent with the rule of law, both in the particular
case of evidence law,
and in general terms.
1. Case Study One: Examples of Evidentiary Privilege
While evidence law involves a lot of judicial discretion,
certain evidentiary privileges serve as useful reminders
that evidence law is
not solely concerned with judicial discretion. An evidentiary privilege
is the right to refuse to disclose, or to allow another person
to
disclose, otherwise admissible, relevant evidence.23 That is,
privileged evidence may be withheld notwithstanding its
usefulness.
Marital privilege is an example of a rule of evidence
that does not require, or allow for, the exercise of judicial discretion.
The
statutory test for the availability of marital privilege sets out that it
covers only communications between a husband and
a wife during their
married
22 For instance, Jon R Waltz “Judicial Discretion in the Admission of Evidence under the Federal Rules of Evidence” (1984) 79 NW U L Rev 1097; and Glen Weissenberger “The Supreme Court and the Interpretation of the Federal Rules of Evidence” (1992) 27 Ariz St LJ 1307.
23 Donald L Mathieson (ed) Cross on Evidence (7ed, Butterworths, Wellington, 2001) (original edition, Sir Rupert Cross, 1963) ch 10.1, p. 291.
22 For instance, Jon R Waltz “Judicial Discretion in the
Admission of Evidence under the Federal Rules of Evidence” (1984) 79 NW U
L Rev 1097; and Glen Weissenberger “The Supreme Court and the
Interpretation of the Federal Rules of Evidence” (1992) 27 Ariz St LJ
1307.
23 Donald L Mathieson (ed) Cross on Evidence
(7ed, Butterworths, Wellington, 2001) (original edition, Sir Rupert Cross,
1963) ch 10.1, p. 291.
relationship.24 It does not extend to de facto relationships and
is only available during the relationship itself. For instance, a widow
cannot
claim the privilege, because her marriage has ceased.25 The
privilege is a creation of statute and is designed to protect the marital
relationship rather than the communication itself.26
The rule as it stands leaves no room for judicial discretion. A Judge
uses a wholly mechanical process of rigid rule application
in order to
determine whether or not marital privilege is available with respect to a
particular piece of evidence.27 The example of marital privilege
demonstrates that evidence law at least partially comprises rigid rules; that
is, while there
may be much discretion in evidence law, this is not because
evidence law is per se, or entirely, incompatible with rigid rules.
Consider now a second class of evidentiary privilege. Section 35 of the Evidence Amendment Act (no 2) 1980 (EAA) provides that in circumstances where a communication was made in the context of a special relationship, and that relationship is in need of protection, the Court has discretion to excuse a witness from answering any question, or producing any document, relating to that communication. This discretion is not unconstrained – in reaching its decision, the Court is required to balance the public interest in disclosure of the evidence against the interest in encouraging the confidence.28 But the parameters imposed by the statutory balancing test cannot disguise that the section confers a judicial discretion rather than imposing a rigid rule. It is not possible on the basis of section 35 to draw up a reliable or exhaustive list of qualifying special relationships since a relationship will only be covered if it is not outweighed by various other countervailing interests. The process of deciding whether the privilege is available is far from mechanical; the enquiry must be conducted on the individual facts of each particular case.29
relationship.24 It does not extend to de facto relationships and
is only available during the relationship itself. For instance, a widow
cannot
claim the privilege, because her marriage has ceased.25 The
privilege is a creation of statute and is designed to protect the marital
relationship rather than the communication itself.26
The rule
as it stands leaves no room for judicial discretion. A Judge uses a wholly
mechanical process of rigid rule application
in order to determine whether or
not marital privilege is available with respect to a particular piece of
evidence.27 The example of marital privilege demonstrates that
evidence law at least partially comprises rigid rules; that is, while there
may be much discretion in evidence law, this is not because evidence law is per
se, or entirely, incompatible with rigid rules.
Consider now a second
class of evidentiary privilege. Section 35 of the Evidence Amendment Act (no 2)
1980 (EAA) provides that in
circumstances where a communication was made in
the context of a special relationship, and that relationship is in need of
protection,
the Court has discretion to excuse a witness from answering any
question, or producing any document, relating to that communication.
This
discretion is not unconstrained – in reaching its decision, the Court is
required to balance the public interest
in disclosure of the evidence
against the interest in encouraging the confidence.28 But the
parameters imposed by the statutory balancing test cannot disguise that the
section confers a judicial discretion rather than
imposing a rigid rule. It is
not possible on the basis of section 35 to draw up a reliable or exhaustive list
of qualifying special
relationships since a relationship will only be covered
if it is not outweighed by various other countervailing interests. The
process
of deciding whether the privilege is available is far from mechanical; the
enquiry must be conducted on the individual
facts of each particular
case.29
24 Evidence Amendment Act (No 2) 1980, section 29.
25 Shenton v Tyler [1939] Ch 620 (CA).
26 See Rumping v Director of Public Prosecutions [1964] AC 814 (HL).
27 Note, this would change if the Evidence Bill 2005 is enacted in its current proposed
form as there will no longer be a specific marital privilege. Marriage, de facto and same- sex relationships would all have the same status and would be assessed on a case by case basis, vesting discretion in judges in respect of marital and other personal relationship privileges.
28 Evidence Amendment Act (No 2) 1980, section 35(1).
29 For instance, see R v Secord [1992] 3 NZLR 570; R v Howse [1983] NZLR 246.
24 Evidence Amendment Act (No 2) 1980, section 29.
25
Shenton v Tyler [1939] Ch 620 (CA).
26 See
Rumping v Director of Public Prosecutions [1964] AC 814 (HL).
27
Note, this would change if the Evidence Bill 2005 is enacted in its current
proposed
form as there will no longer be a specific marital privilege.
Marriage, de facto and same- sex relationships would all have the same
status
and would be assessed on a case by case basis, vesting discretion in judges in
respect of marital and other personal relationship
privileges.
28
Evidence Amendment Act (No 2) 1980, section 35(1).
29 For
instance, see R v Secord [1992] 3 NZLR 570; R v Howse [1983] NZLR
246.
Some privileges then, like marital privilege, are governed by strict,
predictable rules; others, like the section 35 discretion are
discretionary. It
is certain and predictable that marital privilege will be available to
particular witness. For instance, a
de facto wife knows in advance, and with
certainty, that she will not be covered by marital privilege in
respect of any
communication that her de facto husband has made to her in the
course of her relationship. It is not predictable with such certainty
whether, for instance, a probation officer who wishes to protect
confidences made to her by an inmate will be excused
from giving evidence of
these confidences under section 35.30
The observation that one privilege is predictable while the other is not has
some bearing on rule of law considerations. Yet, the
observation does not on
its own lead to a conclusion as to whether or not any particular privilege,
whether rigid rule or
discretion based, is consistent with the rule of law.
Besides predictability, other rule of law values need to be considered. For
instance, the marital privilege rule may be certain, but arguably it is
arbitrary. If its purpose is to protect marital
relationships because
these are socially valuable, it is hard to see why the privilege should
not also extend to
de facto or same-sex relationships or to other
familial relationships such as that between a parent and a child. A more
discretionary test, like under section 35, is better able to adapt to specific
facts. This may be in the interest of fairness
and also the pursuit of
truth.
2. Case Study Two: Relevance Enquiry
Relevance is not directly a question of law but rather a concept arrived at
inductively from experience.31 However, relevance is a necessary
precondition for admissibility; the relevance enquiry is a Judge’s
first step in any
broader admissibility enquiry.
Relevance is a relational concept; it is not meaningful to assert that a fact is relevant unless one articulates what it is relevant to.32 Evidence
Some privileges then, like marital privilege, are governed by strict,
predictable rules; others, like the section 35 discretion are
discretionary. It
is certain and predictable that marital privilege will be available to
particular witness. For instance, a
de facto wife knows in advance, and with
certainty, that she will not be covered by marital privilege in
respect of any
communication that her de facto husband has made to her in the
course of her relationship. It is not predictable with such certainty
whether, for instance, a probation officer who wishes to protect
confidences made to her by an inmate will be excused
from giving evidence of
these confidences under section 35.30
The observation that one
privilege is predictable while the other is not has some bearing on rule of law
considerations. Yet, the
observation does not on its own lead to a
conclusion as to whether or not any particular privilege, whether rigid rule
or
discretion based, is consistent with the rule of law. Besides predictability,
other rule of law values need to be considered. For
instance, the marital
privilege rule may be certain, but arguably it is arbitrary. If its
purpose is to protect marital
relationships because these are socially
valuable, it is hard to see why the privilege should not also extend
to de
facto or same-sex relationships or to other familial
relationships such as that between a parent and a child. A more discretionary
test, like under section 35, is better able to adapt to specific facts. This
may be in the interest of fairness and also the
pursuit of truth.
2. Case Study Two: Relevance Enquiry
Relevance is not directly a question of law but rather a concept arrived
at inductively from experience.31 However, relevance is a necessary
precondition for admissibility; the relevance enquiry is a Judge’s
first step in any
broader admissibility enquiry.
Relevance is a
relational concept; it is not meaningful to assert that a fact is relevant
unless one articulates what it is relevant
to.32
Evidence
30 R v Secord, supra, n. 29.
31 Mathieson, supra, n. 23, ch 1.56, p. 42.
32 Jeremy Bentham Rationale of Judicial Evidence (Hunt & Clarke, London, 1827) in Peter
Murphy (ed) Evidence, Proof, And Facts: A Book of Sources (Oxford University Press, Oxford,
2003), p. 166.
30 R v Secord, supra, n. 29.
31
Mathieson, supra, n. 23, ch 1.56, p. 42.
32 Jeremy Bentham
Rationale of Judicial Evidence (Hunt & Clarke, London, 1827) in
Peter
Murphy (ed) Evidence, Proof, And Facts: A Book of Sources
(Oxford University Press, Oxford,
2003), p. 166.
will be relevant if it has a tendency to prove a fact or conclusion at
issue.33 So, in order to determine whether or not a piece of
evidence is relevant, the judge must first identify the purpose for which any
item of evidence is sought to be admitted. In other words, the judge
must identify the material fact at issue.34 The judge then must
engage in the factual enquiry of whether or not the item of evidence has a
tendency to prove that fact.
Because the relevance enquiry is a factual enquiry, it is often overlooked as
an example of judicial discretion. However,
like most factual
enquiries, it is not wholly mechanical and involves a considerable
degree of flexibility.35 The Judge must identify the dividing line
between facts which are, and are not, too remote from the issue to be relevant.
Inevitably,
the Judge’s own experiences and beliefs may influence his or
her decision about relevance.
Consider the question of whether or not evidence about
a complainant’s sexual history is relevant
in a sexual violation
case. Section 23A of the Evidence Act 1908 imposes a heightened relevance
standard in such situation
– evidence must be of
“such direct relevance” to a fact in issue that to exclude it
would be contrary
to the interests of justice.36 With a little
reflection it is clear however that even a heightened relevance test is far
short of a rigid rule. Judges
must exercise judgment and discretion in
applying such a test.
Consider the following rape case. In R v Taria, the male accused put up the defence that the female complainant had consented to sexual intercourse.37 In support of this argument, defence counsel sought to cross-examine the complainant about “love bites” she had received and shown to her friends a week before the alleged rape. The Judge granted
will be relevant if it has a tendency to prove a fact or conclusion at
issue.33 So, in order to determine whether or not a piece of
evidence is relevant, the judge must first identify the purpose for which any
item of evidence is sought to be admitted. In other words, the judge
must identify the material fact at issue.34 The judge then must
engage in the factual enquiry of whether or not the item of evidence has a
tendency to prove that fact.
Because the relevance enquiry is a factual
enquiry, it is often overlooked as an example of judicial discretion.
However,
like most factual enquiries, it is not wholly mechanical and
involves a considerable degree of flexibility.35 The Judge must
identify the dividing line between facts which are, and are not, too remote from
the issue to be relevant. Inevitably,
the Judge’s own experiences and
beliefs may influence his or her decision about relevance.
Consider
the question of whether or not evidence about a
complainant’s sexual history is relevant
in a sexual violation
case. Section 23A of the Evidence Act 1908 imposes a heightened relevance
standard in such situation
– evidence must be of
“such direct relevance” to a fact in issue that to exclude it
would be contrary
to the interests of justice.36 With a little
reflection it is clear however that even a heightened relevance test is far
short of a rigid rule. Judges
must exercise judgment and discretion in
applying such a test.
Consider the following rape case. In R v
Taria, the male accused put up the defence that the female complainant had
consented to sexual intercourse.37 In support of this argument,
defence counsel sought to cross-examine the complainant about “love
bites” she had received
and shown to her friends a week before the alleged
rape. The Judge granted
33 Definition of relevance, Evidence Bill 2005, cl. 7. See also Sir James Fitzjames Stephen Digest of the Law of Evidence (12ed by Sir Harry Stephen and Lewis Sturge (MacMillan & Co, London, 1948) in Peter Murphy (ed) Evidence, Proof, And Facts: A Book of Sources (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2003) p. 165.
34 John Sopinka, Sidney N Lederman and Alan W Bryant The Law of Evidence in Canada
(Butterworths, Toronto, 1992) p. 1.
35 Jenny McEwan Evidence and the Adversarial Process (2ed, Hart Publishing, Oxford, 1998)
p. 87.
36 Evidence Act 1908, s 23A(3). See also New Zealand Law Commission Evidence Law
Character and Credibility – A Discussion Paper (NZLC PP 27, Wellington, 1997), p. 105.
37 R v Taria (1993) 10 CRNZ 14 (HC).
33 Definition of relevance, Evidence Bill 2005, cl. 7. See also
Sir James Fitzjames Stephen Digest of the Law of Evidence (12ed by Sir
Harry Stephen and Lewis Sturge (MacMillan & Co, London, 1948) in Peter
Murphy (ed) Evidence, Proof, And Facts: A Book of Sources (Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 2003) p. 165.
34 John Sopinka, Sidney N
Lederman and Alan W Bryant The Law of Evidence in
Canada
(Butterworths, Toronto, 1992) p. 1.
35 Jenny McEwan
Evidence and the Adversarial Process (2ed, Hart Publishing, Oxford,
1998)
p. 87.
36 Evidence Act 1908, s 23A(3). See also New
Zealand Law Commission Evidence Law
Character and Credibility
– A Discussion Paper (NZLC PP 27, Wellington, 1997), p.
105.
37 R v Taria (1993) 10 CRNZ 14 (HC).
leave to cross-examine on the ground that the evidence was directly relevant to the facts in issue. Certainly, the Judge’s reasoning is couched in the language of section 23A. But although he rigidly adhered to the test, the test itself is not rigid. Here, the Judge’s decision surely reflected his own views about the complainant’s behaviour and the issue of consent. Presumably, he considered that a complainant who had received love bites and shown them off to others one week earlier was likely to have consented to sex one week later. But if his decision is open to criticism, this is not because he has failed to apply the section
23A heightened relevance standard but rather because some people
would disagree with the factual assumptions that must
have factored into his
decision-making under the standard. Some might find it hard to see how the fact
that some person other than
the accused, or even the accused himself, gave the
complainant love bites one week prior to the alleged rape could be directly
relevant
to the consent at that later time. Other judges might have reached the
opposite conclusion. But, if some other judges would have
found differently in
this case, it is not because they would apply section 23A and the Judge
in Taria would not. Discretion is inherent in any relevance enquiry.
In practice, the ways in which individual judges have applied the
section
23A heightened relevance standard has seen wide variation.38
3. Case Study Three: Hearsay Evidence
Generally stated, the rule against hearsay evidence is as follows:
an assertion other than one made by a person while giving
oral evidence in the
proceedings is inadmissible as evidence of any fact
asserted.39
The rationale for the hearsay rule is broadly that hearsay evidence can be unreliable and so is of less probative value than evidence given directly as oral evidence in proceedings. Unlike oral evidence that is given directly, a reported hearsay statement cannot be subjected to cross-examination.40
leave to cross-examine on the ground that the evidence was directly
relevant to the facts in issue. Certainly, the Judge’s
reasoning is
couched in the language of section 23A. But although he rigidly adhered to the
test, the test itself is not rigid. Here,
the Judge’s decision surely
reflected his own views about the complainant’s behaviour and the
issue of consent.
Presumably, he considered that a complainant who
had received love bites and shown them off to others one week earlier
was likely
to have consented to sex one week later. But if his decision is open to
criticism, this is not because he has failed
to apply the section
23A
heightened relevance standard but rather because some people would
disagree with the factual assumptions that must
have factored into his
decision-making under the standard. Some might find it hard to see how the fact
that some person other than
the accused, or even the accused himself, gave the
complainant love bites one week prior to the alleged rape could be directly
relevant
to the consent at that later time. Other judges might have reached the
opposite conclusion. But, if some other judges would have
found differently in
this case, it is not because they would apply section 23A and the Judge
in Taria would not. Discretion is inherent in any relevance enquiry.
In practice, the ways in which individual judges have applied the
section
23A heightened relevance standard has seen wide variation.38
3. Case Study Three: Hearsay Evidence
Generally stated, the
rule against hearsay evidence is as follows: an assertion other than one
made by a person while giving
oral evidence in the proceedings is inadmissible
as evidence of any fact asserted.39
The rationale for
the hearsay rule is broadly that hearsay evidence can be unreliable and so
is of less probative value than
evidence given directly as oral evidence
in proceedings. Unlike oral evidence that is given directly, a reported
hearsay
statement cannot be subjected to
cross-examination.40
38 See Aileen McColgan “Common Law and the Relevance of Sexual History Evidence” (1996) 16 Oxford J Legal Stud 276.
39 Mathieson, supra, n. 23, ch 1.16, p. 18.
40 AAS Zuckerman The Principles of Criminal Evidence (Clarendon, Oxford, 1989), p. 180.
38 See Aileen McColgan “Common Law and the Relevance of
Sexual History Evidence” (1996) 16 Oxford J Legal Stud 276.
39
Mathieson, supra, n. 23, ch 1.16, p. 18.
40 AAS Zuckerman The
Principles of Criminal Evidence (Clarendon, Oxford, 1989), p.
180.
A rigidly applied hearsay rule has the advantage of certainty. However, it
has disadvantages also, including a risk that the rule
might operate to exclude
reliable as well as unreliable evidence.41 In practice, the rigid
effect of the hearsay exclusionary rule has been mitigated through the
development of exceptions. The EAA
contains a number of narrow exceptions
to the hearsay rule.42 For instance, a hearsay statement about an
assertion made by a person shortly before his or her death can be admissible in
spite
of the general rule against hearsay.43 The maker of the
original statement is now dead and so is unavailable as a witness. The
rationale for admitting a hearsay report
of the original statement is that it
is of probative value, and it is thought unlikely that a dying person
would be motivated
make a false statement. Without this exception,
even if highly relevant and probative, such hearsay statements
would simply be unavailable to the Court.
4. General Residual Exception to the Hearsay Rule
The case of R v Baker marked the beginning of the development in
New Zealand of a common law general residual exception to the hearsay
rule,
as an addition to the narrow exceptions in the EAA.44 In the
case, the prosecution sought to admit hearsay evidence for the purpose
of discrediting the accused’s account
of the night of the killing. Cooke
P acknowledged that the statements were hearsay and that as such they could
only be admitted
via some exception to the hearsay exclusionary rule. No
existing exception applied. However, Cooke P, with whom Ellis J
specifically
agreed, considered that:
“At least in a case such as the present it may be more helpful to go straight to basics and ask whether in the particular circumstances it is reasonably safe and of sufficient relevance to admit the evidence notwithstanding the dangers against which the hearsay rule guards.”45
A rigidly applied hearsay rule has the advantage of certainty. However, it
has disadvantages also, including a risk that the rule
might operate to exclude
reliable as well as unreliable evidence.41 In practice, the rigid
effect of the hearsay exclusionary rule has been mitigated through the
development of exceptions. The EAA
contains a number of narrow exceptions
to the hearsay rule.42 For instance, a hearsay statement about an
assertion made by a person shortly before his or her death can be admissible in
spite
of the general rule against hearsay.43 The maker of the
original statement is now dead and so is unavailable as a witness. The
rationale for admitting a hearsay report
of the original statement is that it
is of probative value, and it is thought unlikely that a dying person
would be motivated
make a false statement. Without this exception,
even if highly relevant and probative, such hearsay statements
would simply be unavailable to the Court.
4. General Residual Exception to the Hearsay Rule
The case of
R v Baker marked the beginning of the development in New Zealand of
a common law general residual exception to the hearsay rule,
as an
addition to the narrow exceptions in the EAA.44 In the case, the
prosecution sought to admit hearsay evidence for the purpose of
discrediting the accused’s account
of the night of the killing. Cooke P
acknowledged that the statements were hearsay and that as such they could
only be admitted
via some exception to the hearsay exclusionary rule. No
existing exception applied. However, Cooke P, with whom Ellis J
specifically
agreed, considered that:
“At least in a case such as the present it may be more helpful to go
straight to basics and ask whether in the particular
circumstances it is
reasonably safe and of sufficient relevance to admit the evidence
notwithstanding the dangers against
which the hearsay rule
guards.”45
41 Zuckerman, supra, n. 40, p. 182.
42 Evidence Amendment Act (no 2) 1980, sections 3 and 8-14.
43 Codified in Evidence Amendment Act (No 2) 1980, section 14.
44 R v Baker [1989] NZCA 62; [1989] 1 NZLR 738 (CA).
45 R v Baker, supra, n. 44, p. 741 Cooke P.
41 Zuckerman, supra, n. 40, p. 182.
42 Evidence
Amendment Act (no 2) 1980, sections 3 and 8-14.
43 Codified in Evidence
Amendment Act (No 2) 1980, section 14.
44 R v Baker
[1989] NZCA 62; [1989] 1 NZLR 738 (CA).
45 R v Baker, supra, n. 44, p. 741
Cooke P.
Cooke P suggested that this enquiry was essentially “a question of
degree”.46 Effectively, he was suggesting that a judge has a
discretion to admit hearsay evidence when he or she considers it to be
sufficiently
cogent and decides it is “reasonably safe” in all the
circumstances to admit it. He said that in such instances, a
judge should issue
a warning to the jury, alerting them to the dangers associated with
hearsay evidence.47
This discretion was further developed in R v Bain.48
The evidence in that case was of statements made by a third party to a
witness which were said to raise an inference that someone
other than the
accused had a motive for the killings. Thomas J delivered the judgment
of the Court. He considered that
Baker had decided that evidence that is
sufficiently reliable and relevant may be admissible, despite being
hearsay, because it
is not associated with high risks of “the perceived
dangers of hearsay evidence”.49 Whether or not to
admit hearsay evidence “is necessarily a matter of degree, and will
almost invariably be decided by the
application of the trial judge’s
discretion having regard to the overall interests of justice”.50
Thomas J considered that, although the EAA imposes certain narrow
legislative exceptions to the hearsay rule, it does not follow
that “any
judicial development of the rule to meet changing circumstances and ensure
that the rules of evidence serve
the ends of justice is
precluded”.51
The case of R v Manase later provided a unanimous, bench of five, canonical statement of the general residual discretion to admit hearsay evidence.52 The discretion turns on three elements: relevance, inability and reliability.53 In addition, as with any evidence, hearsay evidence should not be admitted where its probative value is outweighed by its illegitimate prejudicial effect.54 Exercise of the discretion is a balancing
Cooke P suggested that this enquiry was essentially “a question of
degree”.46 Effectively, he was suggesting that a judge has a
discretion to admit hearsay evidence when he or she considers it to be
sufficiently
cogent and decides it is “reasonably safe” in all the
circumstances to admit it. He said that in such instances, a
judge should issue
a warning to the jury, alerting them to the dangers associated with
hearsay evidence.47
This discretion was further developed
in R v Bain.48 The evidence in that case was of statements
made by a third party to a witness which were said to raise an inference that
someone
other than the accused had a motive for the killings. Thomas J
delivered the judgment of the Court. He considered that
Baker had
decided that evidence that is sufficiently reliable and relevant may be
admissible, despite being hearsay, because it
is not associated with high
risks of “the perceived dangers of hearsay evidence”.49
Whether or not to admit hearsay evidence “is necessarily a
matter of degree, and will almost invariably be decided by the
application of
the trial judge’s discretion having regard to the overall interests of
justice”.50 Thomas J considered that, although the EAA imposes
certain narrow legislative exceptions to the hearsay rule, it does not follow
that “any judicial development of the rule to meet changing
circumstances and ensure that the rules of evidence serve
the ends of
justice is precluded”.51
The case of R v Manase
later provided a unanimous, bench of five, canonical statement of the
general residual discretion to admit hearsay evidence.52 The
discretion turns on three elements: relevance, inability and
reliability.53 In addition, as with any evidence, hearsay
evidence should not be admitted where its probative value is outweighed by its
illegitimate
prejudicial effect.54 Exercise of the discretion is a
balancing
46 R v Baker, supra, n. 44, p. 741 Cooke P.
47 R v Baker, supra, n. 44, p. 741 Cooke P; Mathieson, supra, n. 19, ch 16.28A, p. 59.
48 R v Bain [1996] 1 NZLR 129 (CA).
49 R v Bain, supra, n. 48, p. 132 Thomas J.
50 R v Bain, supra, n. 48, p. 133 Thomas J.
51 R v Bain, supra, n. 48, p. 134 Thomas J.
52 R v Manase [2001] 2 NZLR 197 (CA).
53 R v Manase, supra, n. 52, para. 30 Tipping J.
54 R v Manase, supra, n. 52, para. 31 Tipping J.
46 R v Baker, supra, n. 44, p. 741 Cooke P.
47
R v Baker, supra, n. 44, p. 741 Cooke P; Mathieson, supra, n. 19,
ch 16.28A, p. 59.
48 R v Bain [1996] 1 NZLR 129
(CA).
49 R v Bain, supra, n. 48, p. 132 Thomas
J.
50 R v Bain, supra, n. 48, p. 133 Thomas J.
51
R v Bain, supra, n. 48, p. 134 Thomas J.
52 R v Manase
[2001] 2 NZLR 197 (CA).
53 R v Manase, supra, n.
52, para. 30 Tipping J.
54 R v Manase, supra, n. 52, para. 31
Tipping J.
exercise then; it is not purely mechanical and thus not necessarily
predictable.
The development of the general residual discretion was motivated by the
problems associated with a too rigid hearsay rule. If the
best or only available
evidence happens to be hearsay evidence, then to necessarily exclude that
evidence because it is hearsay
seems too high a price to pay for certainty.
The application of a rigid hearsay rule may be predictable, but it does
not further other evidence law values such as the aim to discover truth and to
apply the law to the facts. The rule of law requires
a degree of certainty and
predictability, but it also requires procedural due process and fairness. It is
worth remembering that
the rule against hearsay can operate to exclude not
just hearsay evidence sought to be admitted by the prosecution or stronger
party; it could equally operate to exclude an accused’s best defence, if
that happens to be based on a hearsay statement.
5. Case Study Four: Probative Value and Prejudicial Effect
The law of evidence contains many specific admissibility rules and exceptions
such as those illustrated by the above case studies.
It is important to
remember, however, that these specific rules and exceptions are
subject to a final, general judicial
discretion: a judge can reject otherwise
admissible evidence on the ground that the prejudicial effect of its admission
would outweigh
its probative value.55
Balancing the probative value of a piece of evidence against its prejudicial effect involves weighing a number of factors. A dominant factor is whether or not the piece of evidence is likely to induce jurors to reason emotionally or irrationally or to overvalue the evidence to the exclusion of other relevant evidence in the case.56 It has been said that the focus of this enquiry is misguided because, if by prejudicial effect we mean illegitimate or unfair prejudicial effect on the accused, then, from the point of view of procedural due process and natural justice, it is not clear that probative value should ever be allowed to outweigh
exercise then; it is not purely mechanical and thus not necessarily
predictable.
The development of the general residual discretion was
motivated by the problems associated with a too rigid hearsay rule. If the
best
or only available evidence happens to be hearsay evidence, then to necessarily
exclude that evidence because it is hearsay
seems too high a price to pay
for certainty. The application of a rigid hearsay rule may be
predictable, but it does
not further other evidence law values such as the aim
to discover truth and to apply the law to the facts. The rule of law requires
a
degree of certainty and predictability, but it also requires procedural due
process and fairness. It is worth remembering that
the rule against hearsay
can operate to exclude not just hearsay evidence sought to be admitted by
the prosecution or stronger
party; it could equally operate to exclude an
accused’s best defence, if that happens to be based on a hearsay
statement.
5. Case Study Four: Probative Value and Prejudicial Effect
The
law of evidence contains many specific admissibility rules and exceptions such
as those illustrated by the above case studies.
It is important to remember,
however, that these specific rules and exceptions are subject to a
final, general judicial
discretion: a judge can reject otherwise admissible
evidence on the ground that the prejudicial effect of its admission would
outweigh
its probative value.55
Balancing the probative
value of a piece of evidence against its prejudicial effect involves
weighing a number of
factors. A dominant factor is whether or not the piece of
evidence is likely to induce jurors to reason emotionally or irrationally
or to
overvalue the evidence to the exclusion of other relevant evidence in the
case.56 It has been said that the focus of this enquiry is misguided
because, if by prejudicial effect we mean illegitimate or unfair
prejudicial effect on the accused, then, from the point of view of
procedural due process and natural justice, it is not clear
that probative
value should ever be allowed to outweigh
55 Evidence Amendment Act (No 2) 1980, section 18. Note, Evidence Bill 2005, cl 8(a), if enacted, would preserve this discretion. Note also, there is no converse discretion to admit otherwise inadmissible evidence on the grounds that its probative value outweighs its prejudicial effect: Myers v DPP [1965] AC 1001, p. 1024 (HL) Lord Reid.
56 Mengler, supra, n. 22, p. 442.
55 Evidence Amendment Act (No 2) 1980, section 18. Note, Evidence
Bill 2005, cl 8(a), if enacted, would preserve this discretion. Note
also, there
is no converse discretion to admit otherwise inadmissible evidence on the
grounds that its probative value outweighs its prejudicial effect: Myers v
DPP [1965] AC 1001, p. 1024 (HL) Lord Reid.
56 Mengler, supra, n.
22, p. 442.
prejudice.57 A separate criticism is that the complex
weighing of probative value and prejudicial effect accords judges
too much flexibility and discretion at the risk of inconsistent
decisions.58
Both criticisms are serious from a rule of law perspective. However, the
consequences of the first may be more readily contained.
If the
balancing exercise fails to protect an accused’s right to a fair trial, it
is at least logically possible to recast
the test such that its focus is whether
or not admission of certain evidence is fair. The second criticism, that the
enquiry vests
too much discretion in judges cannot be avoided in this way. If
all rules are open textured and rules and principles are different
in degree,
not kind, then discretion and uncertainty will always be present in
evidence law, no matter how we reformulate
its details.
C: Evidence Law and the Rule of Law: Is Evidence Law a Special
Case?
The case studies discussed above illustrate that evidence law not only
allows but actually requires the exercise of a great
deal of judicial
discretion. Evidence law contains some rigid rules, such as those
governing the availability of marital
privilege; such rules are certain at
least, but they can sometimes fall short in terms of fairness. For this
reason, rigid rules,
like the one against admitting hearsay evidence,
often spawn exceptions. These exceptions are designed to accommodate
specific circumstances which mean that a bare prohibition of
hearsay statements is unfair. Aside from exceptions
to specific
admissibility rules, as we have seen, judges have an ultimate discretion
to refuse to admit otherwise
admissible evidence if its prejudicial
effect is likely to be higher than its probative value.
Two questions arise from the observation that evidence law contains constrained judicial discretion: first, the question of whether or not judicial discretion is consistent with the rule of law in the particular case of evidence law; secondly, the question of whether or not the two are consistent in general terms.
prejudice.57 A separate criticism is that the complex
weighing of probative value and prejudicial effect accords judges
too much flexibility and discretion at the risk of inconsistent
decisions.58
Both criticisms are serious from a rule of law
perspective. However, the consequences of the first may be more readily
contained.
If the balancing exercise fails to protect an accused’s
right to a fair trial, it is at least logically possible to recast
the test such
that its focus is whether or not admission of certain evidence is fair. The
second criticism, that the enquiry vests
too much discretion in judges cannot be
avoided in this way. If all rules are open textured and rules and principles are
different
in degree, not kind, then discretion and uncertainty will
always be present in evidence law, no matter how we reformulate
its
details.
C: Evidence Law and the Rule of Law: Is Evidence Law a Special
Case?
The case studies discussed above illustrate that evidence law
not only allows but actually requires the exercise of a great
deal of
judicial discretion. Evidence law contains some rigid rules, such as
those governing the availability of marital
privilege; such rules are certain
at least, but they can sometimes fall short in terms of fairness. For this
reason, rigid rules,
like the one against admitting hearsay evidence,
often spawn exceptions. These exceptions are designed to accommodate
specific circumstances which mean that a bare prohibition of
hearsay statements is unfair. Aside from exceptions
to specific
admissibility rules, as we have seen, judges have an ultimate discretion
to refuse to admit otherwise
admissible evidence if its prejudicial
effect is likely to be higher than its probative value.
Two questions
arise from the observation that evidence law contains constrained judicial
discretion: first, the question
of whether or not judicial discretion is
consistent with the rule of law in the particular case of evidence law;
secondly, the
question of whether or not the two are consistent in general
terms.
57 See Don Mathias “Probative Value, Illegitimate Prejudice and the Accused’s Right to a
Fair Trial” (2005) 29 Crim LJ 8.
58 See Mathias, supra, n. 57, p. 8.
57 See Don Mathias “Probative Value, Illegitimate Prejudice
and the Accused’s Right to a
Fair Trial” (2005) 29 Crim LJ
8.
58 See Mathias, supra, n. 57, p. 8.
Evidence law either is, or is not, a special case from a rule of law
perspective. Evidence law is a procedural or “adjective”,
rather
than a substantive, form of law.59 Substantive law declares
the rights and duties of those who are subject to the law; adjective law
relates to the remedial agencies
and procedure through which those rights are
maintained.60
To say that evidence is not a special case would also be to say that
considerations of consistency and predictability are equally
as important in
relation to procedural law as they are to substantive law.61 However,
one could instead assert that the distinction between procedure and substance
is important from a rule of law perspective.
Conceivably then, even if
lack of predictability is problematic for substantive areas of law, the
position might be different
with regard to procedural evidence
law.
There is something to be said for the claim that evidence law is just such
a special case. It makes some sense to say that individuals
should know their
substantive rights and obligations in advance so that they can plan their
conduct – even if most criminals
do not in fact perform a conscious
cost/benefit analysis before deciding to break the law, the idea of
planning one’s
life around substantive legal obligations is not absurd.
The claim, however, that individuals need to be able to predict, with
certainty,
what forms of evidence might be admitted as proof of their wrongdoing, should
they choose to break a substantive law,
seems more tenuous. This type of
informed decision-making seems, at once, much less likely to ever be attempted
by an individual,
and also less strikingly important. If we need to know in
advance know how a procedural law will operate, this is only because
it impacts
on the predictability of the substantive law.62
1. The Breadth of Evidence Law
Another possible reason for suggesting that evidence law is a special case from a rule of law perspective is that it is incredibly broad in
Evidence law either is, or is not, a special case from a rule of law
perspective. Evidence law is a procedural or “adjective”,
rather
than a substantive, form of law.59 Substantive law declares
the rights and duties of those who are subject to the law; adjective law
relates to the remedial agencies
and procedure through which those rights are
maintained.60
To say that evidence is not a special case
would also be to say that considerations of consistency and predictability are
equally
as important in relation to procedural law as they are to substantive
law.61 However, one could instead assert that the distinction between
procedure and substance is important from a rule of law perspective.
Conceivably then, even if lack of predictability is problematic for
substantive areas of law, the position might be different
with regard
to procedural evidence law.
There is something to be said for the claim
that evidence law is just such a special case. It makes some sense to say that
individuals
should know their substantive rights and obligations in advance so
that they can plan their conduct – even if most criminals
do not in fact
perform a conscious cost/benefit analysis before deciding to break the
law, the idea of planning one’s
life around substantive legal obligations
is not absurd. The claim, however, that individuals need to be able to predict,
with certainty,
what forms of evidence might be admitted as proof of their
wrongdoing, should they choose to break a substantive law, seems more
tenuous.
This type of informed decision-making seems, at once, much less likely to ever
be attempted by an individual, and also
less strikingly important. If we need
to know in advance know how a procedural law will operate, this is only because
it impacts
on the predictability of the substantive law.62
1. The Breadth of Evidence Law
Another possible reason for suggesting that evidence law is a
special case from a rule of law perspective is that it is
incredibly
broad in
59 L Jonathan Cohen “Freedom of Proof” in William Twining (ed) Facts in Law ( Franz
Steiner Verlag GMBH, Wiesbaden, 1983), p. 3.
60 Garner, supra, n. 6, pp. 44, 1244, 1470.
61 Cohen, supra, n. 56, p. 2.
62 See Mengler, supra, n. 18, p. 461.
59 L Jonathan Cohen “Freedom of Proof” in William
Twining (ed) Facts in Law ( Franz
Steiner Verlag GMBH, Wiesbaden,
1983), p. 3.
60 Garner, supra, n. 6, pp. 44, 1244,
1470.
61 Cohen, supra, n. 56, p. 2.
62 See
Mengler, supra, n. 18, p. 461.
scope. Its scope is broad because evidence law is a major part of the
procedural underpinnings according to which substantive
legal issues are
litigated, decided and enforced. This paper has focussed on
evidence law case studies from a criminal
law context, but of course
admissibility questions arise in relation to any area of law that come before
the Court. Evidence
law covers the whole range of areas of law: criminal,
family, public, tort, environmental, tax law, and so on.
Furthermore, our laws of evidence allow primarily circumstantial
evidence to be admitted as proof. Ever since we abandoned
trial by ordeal,
in which God was in a sense assumed to be permanently available as a
compellable witness, we have taken
it upon ourselves to decide legal questions
of guilt and innocence.63 We employ inductive rather than
deductive methods of proof. Arguably the procedural rules governing the
admissibility of this inductive
evidence are a very special case indeed.
2. A Special Case or Merely Striking?
Evidence law’s breadth and incorporation of circumstantial
proof means that it is a field in which it is impossible
to map out completely
using fixed, predetermined rules. There are simply too many possible
combinations of evidential facts, arising
in legal contexts too numerous, for us
to ever cover every possible admissibility eventuality in rule form in advance.
It is not
merely a contingent fact that evidence law involves so much judicial
discretion; from a practical point of view, this is
a necessary
fact.
The extraordinary breadth of evidence law and its incorporation of circumstantial proof are alone insufficient to make evidence law a special case from a rule of law perspective, however. As discussed earlier, rules and standards are not polar opposites but range across the same continuum. Rules are necessarily open-textured, and discretion is constrained to some degree.64 The certainty with which the results of rules and principles can be predicted in advance may vary, but this is a difference of degree rather than of kind. Despite initial appearances then, evidence law is not a special, but rather a striking, case. Evidence
scope. Its scope is broad because evidence law is a major part of the
procedural underpinnings according to which substantive
legal issues are
litigated, decided and enforced. This paper has focussed on
evidence law case studies from a criminal
law context, but of course
admissibility questions arise in relation to any area of law that come before
the Court. Evidence
law covers the whole range of areas of law: criminal,
family, public, tort, environmental, tax law, and so on.
Furthermore,
our laws of evidence allow primarily circumstantial evidence to be
admitted as proof. Ever since we abandoned
trial by ordeal, in which God
was in a sense assumed to be permanently available as a compellable
witness, we have taken
it upon ourselves to decide legal questions of guilt
and innocence.63 We employ inductive rather than deductive methods
of proof. Arguably the procedural rules governing the admissibility of this
inductive
evidence are a very special case indeed.
2. A Special Case or Merely Striking?
Evidence law’s
breadth and incorporation of circumstantial proof means that it is a
field in which it is impossible
to map out completely using fixed, predetermined
rules. There are simply too many possible combinations of evidential facts,
arising
in legal contexts too numerous, for us to ever cover every possible
admissibility eventuality in rule form in advance. It is not
merely a contingent
fact that evidence law involves so much judicial discretion; from a
practical point of view, this is
a necessary fact.
The extraordinary
breadth of evidence law and its incorporation of circumstantial proof are
alone insufficient to make evidence
law a special case from a rule of
law perspective, however. As discussed earlier, rules and standards are not
polar opposites
but range across the same continuum. Rules are necessarily
open-textured, and discretion is constrained to some degree.64 The
certainty with which the results of rules and principles can be predicted in
advance may vary, but this is a difference of degree
rather than of kind.
Despite initial appearances then, evidence law is not a special, but rather a
striking, case. Evidence
63 Cohen, supra, n. 59, p. 6.
64 Sustein, supra, n. 8, p. 960.
63 Cohen, supra, n. 59, p. 6.
64 Sustein, supra, n. 8,
p. 960.
law is remarkably full of discretion, and as such it provides case-studies
which are particularly striking from the point of view
of certain rule of law
principles. However, examples of discretion can also be found in almost any
area of substantive or procedural
law.
Since evidence law is not a special case from a rule of law perspective, we
again return to our definitional question: is the rule
of law the strict notion
of rule by legal rules only; or, is the rule of law a wider and more complicated
concept which can accommodate
principles and discretion as well as
rules?
3. The Rule of Law as a Useful and Accurate Theory
The rule of law can be viewed as a principle or an ideal. Sometimes, ideals
cannot be given literal effect in practice; we aspire
to the ideal but in
practice accept some variation from it. If we choose a strict rule of law
definition that accommodates only rigid
rules and not judicial discretion, then
the concept is an aspirational ideal: in practice, no legal system can be
utterly predictable
and free from discretion. Thus, under a strict definition,
no legal system, in practice, will actually have the rule of law.
Yet, this does not seem to be how we employ the concept in our
discourse. Not all countries have the rule of law, but
we do seem to think
that some do. Indeed, New Zealand is a fairly respectable candidate
for generally adhering to the
rule of law. Yet, as we have seen, New
Zealand evidence law, as well as the rest of its laws, are more or less
open-textured;
there is considerable uncertainty in New Zealand law because of
this.
The role of theories and theoretical discourse is to help us make sense of things or phenomena in the world. While it would beg the question to assume that our ordinary usages and understandings of a concept like the rule of law are correct and accurate, it is reasonable for us to be suspicious of a theory which defines the concept in a way that is radically divergent from our ordinary understanding. A definition of the rule of law that is completely different from what we think we mean when we utter the phrase looks suspiciously like a definition of something different altogether.
law is remarkably full of discretion, and as such it provides case-studies
which are particularly striking from the point of view
of certain rule of law
principles. However, examples of discretion can also be found in almost any
area of substantive or procedural
law.
Since evidence law is not a
special case from a rule of law perspective, we again return to our definitional
question: is the rule
of law the strict notion of rule by legal rules only; or,
is the rule of law a wider and more complicated concept which can accommodate
principles and discretion as well as rules?
3. The Rule of Law as a Useful and Accurate Theory
The rule of
law can be viewed as a principle or an ideal. Sometimes, ideals cannot be given
literal effect in practice; we aspire
to the ideal but in practice accept some
variation from it. If we choose a strict rule of law definition that
accommodates only rigid
rules and not judicial discretion, then the concept is
an aspirational ideal: in practice, no legal system can be utterly predictable
and free from discretion. Thus, under a strict definition, no legal system, in
practice, will actually have the rule of law.
Yet, this does not seem
to be how we employ the concept in our discourse. Not all countries
have the rule of law, but
we do seem to think that some do. Indeed, New
Zealand is a fairly respectable candidate for generally adhering to the
rule of law. Yet, as we have seen, New Zealand evidence law, as well as the
rest of its laws, are more or less open-textured;
there is considerable
uncertainty in New Zealand law because of this.
The role of theories and
theoretical discourse is to help us make sense of things or phenomena in the
world. While it would beg the
question to assume that our ordinary usages and
understandings of a concept like the rule of law are correct and accurate, it
is reasonable for us to be suspicious of a theory which defines the
concept in a way that is radically divergent from
our ordinary
understanding. A definition of the rule of law that is completely different
from what we think we mean when we utter
the phrase looks suspiciously
like a definition of something different altogether.
This is the theoretical problem with the strict, “rules only”
definition of the rule of law. A broader, even if
more complex,
definition better accords with what we seem to mean by the rule of law, and so
is better on theoretical grounds.
Such a definition is also
preferable on pragmatic grounds. An aspirational ideal which can never be
achieved in practice
is likely to be less of a motivation to strive for a good
legal system than an ideal which is attainable with some hard work.
Conclusion
Rules and principles are not polar opposites; in practice, they are different in degree only. While the prevalence of discretion in evidence law is striking, no area of law can escape some degree of discretion and uncertainty. This paper began by proposing a very general working definition of the rule of law. Building on that initial definition, this paper has argued for a broad definition of the rule of law which can accommodate and account for judicial discretion. Such a definition is preferable to a narrow, “rules only” definition from both a theoretical and pragmatic perspective.
This is the theoretical problem with the strict, “rules only”
definition of the rule of law. A broader, even if
more complex,
definition better accords with what we seem to mean by the rule of law, and so
is better on theoretical grounds.
Such a definition is also
preferable on pragmatic grounds. An aspirational ideal which can never be
achieved in practice
is likely to be less of a motivation to strive for a good
legal system than an ideal which is attainable with some hard work.
Conclusion
Rules and principles are not polar opposites;
in practice, they are different in degree only. While the prevalence of
discretion
in evidence law is striking, no area of law can escape some degree of
discretion and uncertainty. This paper began by proposing a
very general working
definition of the rule of law. Building on that initial definition,
this paper has argued for a broad
definition of the rule of law which can
accommodate and account for judicial discretion. Such a definition is
preferable to a
narrow, “rules only” definition from both a
theoretical and pragmatic perspective.
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/NZLawStuJl/2006/8.html