![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
New Zealand Law Students Journal |
Last Updated: 24 October 2012
COMPULSORY TREATMENT OF NON-DANGEROUS MENTAL HEALTH PATIENTS IN NEW ZEALAND
MATTHEW MCKILLOP*
Involuntary treatment under the Mental Health (Compulsory Assessment and
Treatment) Act 1992 is available where a person has
a seriously
diminished capacity for selfcare due to an abnormal state of mind.
This creates a unique interpretive
challenge for Courts, clinicians
and the Mental Health Review Tribunal, where the right of an individual to
withhold
consent to medical treatment may be limited to some extent due to the
requirements of effective independent living in the community.
Introduction
The right to liberty of the person has been described as “the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilised men.”1
To traditional liberal theorists, the only justifiable limitation of
a person’s liberty is “to prevent harm
to others. His own good,
either physical or moral, is not a sufficient
warrant.”2
New Zealand’s primary mental health legislation, the Mental Health
(Compulsory Assessment and Treatment) Act 1992 (MH(CAT)
Act), provides for
compulsory treatment where a person poses a serious danger to the health
or safety of himself or others
due to a mental disorder. Many
jurisdictions go no further than this: the United Kingdom Mental Health
Act of 1983,
for example, provides for compulsory treatment on these grounds
only.3 The policy in such jurisdictions appears to be that once a
mentally ill person is no longer a
* Finalist for BSc/LLB (Hons), University of Otago. This is a revised version of an article written under the supervision of Professor John Dawson during a research scholarship in January 2010. I would like to acknowledge Professor Dawson’s invaluable input in
helping this article reach its final form.
1 Olmstead v United States [1928] USSC 133; (1928) 277 US 438 at 478
2 Mill, J. S., On Liberty (3rd ed., Norton, 1975) 10-11
3 The criteria for both compulsory inpatient treatment (s 3(2)(c)) and community
treatment (s 17A(5)(b)) require that treatment be “necessary for [the
patient’s] health or safety or for the protection
of other
persons”.
danger to the health or safety of themselves or others, their activities are
no longer the concern of mental health service providers.
This is not the case in New Zealand. In addition to patients who
present some danger, the MH(CAT) Act allows
for compulsory
treatment where a mentally disordered person shows a
seriously diminished capacity for self-care. Despite the objections of
liberal theorists, I hope to show through case studies that such a law
is generally justifiable.
However, it must be carefully moderated
to avoid unnecessary and dangerous encroachment on the autonomy of
the
person. In this paper I will first assess current judicial thinking on the
meaning of “seriously diminished capacity
for self-care”. I
will then propose an interpretation of the enactment consistent with the
patient’s right to autonomy
(and the limitations on that right), and
discuss how difficult categories of cases might have been better decided by
taking account
of the rights of the patient and the legal framework of the
MH(CAT) Act. I will also compare how diminished self-care
is
considered under the similar Victorian regime.
A. Current Thoughts on Diminished Self-care
Long-term compulsory treatment of a mental health patient can only be
instituted if that person is mentally disordered, according to the
definition provided in s 2 of the MH(CAT) Act:
2 Interpretation
(1) In this Act, unless the context otherwise requires,—
Mental disorder, in relation to any person, means an abnormal state of mind (whether of a continuous or an intermittent nature), characterised by delusions, or by disorders of mood or perception or volition or cognition, of such a degree that it—
(a) Poses a serious danger to the health or safety of that person or of others; or
(b) Seriously diminishes the capacity of that person to take care of himself or herself;— (emphasis added)
and mentally disordered, in relation to any such person, has a
corresponding meaning
The first ‘limb’ of this definition (ending at the word
“cognition”) requires a person to have an
abnormal state of mind,
characterised by at least one of the disorders of mental function listed. The
second “limb” requires
that the abnormal state of mind give rise to
serious danger to self or to others, or a seriously diminished capacity for
self-care.
It is the latter part of the second limb contained in paragraph (b)
that is the main subject of this paper.
The Mental Health Review Tribunal, constituted under the MH(CAT) Act, is the
primary body dealing with reviews of a patient’s
condition where a
compulsory treatment order is in place, and so has often considered the meaning
of “mental disorder”.
Paragraph (b) of this definition has
consistently presented as particularly challenging. The Tribunal rarely uses the
rather awkward
phrasing of the MH(CAT) Act, instead preferring the
formulation “seriously diminished capacity for self-care”.
This
paper concerns patients subject to and being assessed for inpatient and
community-based compulsory treatment orders made under
s 28 of the MH(CAT)
Act. It will not consider patients with special patient or restricted
patient status.
Whether or not capacity for self-care is seriously diminished has been
a question of judgment particular to the facts of each case. It cannot be better
couched in other terms, except
that there should not be a bright line between
“serious” and “minor” as the Mental Health Review
Tribunal suggested in the application of TJF,4 but rather a
spectrum of diminished capacity on which “serious” somewhere lies.
Seriousness of diminished capacity
may be assessed on a four-part
framework examining the nature of the harm involved, and its
magnitude,
imminence, and frequency.5
1. Capactiy
More challenging are the meanings of diminished capacity and of
self-care. It has long been recognised that diminished capacity cannot be
a solely subjective measure;6 were this the case, the very wealthy
or intelligent
4 Re TJF (MHRT 07/037) 27 April 2007 at para 26
5 This test is primarily used in assessing serious danger to the health or safety of self or others, but has also been endorsed in the assessment of seriously diminished capacity for self care: Re MG (MHRT 09/009) 6 March 2009 at para 54.
6 Re C (unreported) DC Auckland, CAT 132/99, 28 August 2000,
Thorburn DCJ at 9
could feasibly be considered to have reduced capacity due to an
abnormal state of mind while living quite comfortably
on a severely
reduced income, or working happily in an occupation entirely devoid of
intellectual pursuits. Given how self-care
has been defined (see below), such a
reduced standard of living might well impact on the essentials of self-care.
Similar dangers
are inherent to a purely objective definition of self-care, but
at the other end of the scale, where persons with a low normal capacity
for
self-care might be compulsorily treated for not meeting an agreed minimum
common standard.
Capacity for self-care is unique to the individual; the Tribunal often
recognises the unique skills and talents of an
applicant before it.
Despite this, a certain minimum capacity has been generally considered
sufficient in all but the most exceptional
cases, as there is a
“broad commonality” between the minimum capacities of most
members of the community.7 In re C, the Court
described a mixed objective/subjective test of a “minimum standard of
effective self-care for a person of
the patient’s circumstances and
background.”8 This test has often been adopted by the Mental
Health Review Tribunal,9 and is preferable to the apparently
subjective test described by the Tribunal in one recent case.10
Fringe cases are most often persons with a below- average
capacity independent of any abnormal state of mind, such as those
with an intellectual or physical disability, or frailty
due to age, rather
than those of particular wealth or intelligence.11 These are the
people most likely to be negatively affected by a purely objective test. Because
the fringe cases tend to concern
those people with a low baseline
capacity for self-care independent of a mental disorder, I conclude
that the
Tribunal demonstrates a tendency to favour objectivity
over subjectivity. In light of the comparative ability for self-
care of those
most affected by either test, this outcome appears
preferable.
7 Re AVHM (MHRT 08/110) 25 August 2008 at para 39
8 Re C, above n 6
9 Re SC (MHRT 07/135) 13 December 2007; Re JRS (MHRT 08/055) 5 May 2008
10 Re AVHM, above n 7, at para 36
11 I do not have any statistical information that would confirm
this view, so I base this assertion on having read approximately 650
Mental
Health Review Tribunal decisions.
2. Self-care
Self-care has a long-established definition in Review Tribunal proceedings.
It is not limited to the basic necessities of
survival (activities of
daily living such as food, shelter, hygiene and medication) but includes
“the multiplicity of other
needs such as achieving financial security,
maintaining proper social relationships, maintaining stable accommodation and
seeking
out...the assistance of others...concerning health and
lifestyle.”12 Self-care has been said to embrace all of
“the higher complexities of modern living”13 and the
“ability to cope adequately in the community.”14
Such a vague definition is more helpfully limited by what it is
not, rather than what it includes. Self-care is not simply
that which is in the
“best interests” of a patient, where he behaves in some way that
makes him a nuisance to others.15 Nor does it include
provision for “the capacity to find happiness in life and fulfil
potential”;16 these are considered to be private and
individual matters independent of any mental disorder.
Counter-intuitively, self-care can also be regarded as those essential
functions that can be “reasonably readily provided or
addressed by
others.”17 The degree of outside care available to a patient
is a relevant factor in the mental disorder test. Where the support of
whanau
or friends is present to adequately account for diminished capacity or
the risks posed to self or others, a person who
is otherwise mentally
disordered may be released.18
3. Ambiguous Criteria and Tough Cases
The correctness of the Mental Health Review Tribunal’s interpretation
of the mental disorder definition is far from
settled. The individual
words of the definition each have a multitude of possible meanings,
12 Decision 324/95 (NRT 324/95) 14 June 1995
13 Re AVHM, above n 7, at para 41
14 324/95 above n 12
15 Re SFC (MHRT 2002/032) 4 November 2002
16 Re AVHM, above n 7, at para 42; see also Re TJF, above n 3, at para 13
17 Re AVHM, above n 7, at para 43
18 Re TRT (MHRT 09/078) 14 August 2009
and Tribunal cases are often characterised by contention between responsible
clinicians and patients’ counsel as to whether
the applicant’s
behaviours can be considered to seriously diminish that
person’s capacity for self-care.
Serious, for example, might mean
“significant or worrying in terms of danger or risks” or
“more than minor”19 or possibly “not
slight”; diminished capacity could require a subjective assessment
of the patient’s usual capacities, or an objective view of reasonable
capacity; self-care might include the bare essentials of life such as
accommodation, sanitation and food, or could include all the
ingredients
needed for self-actualisation such as relationships and other
appropriate social conduct. As I stated above, the meaning of serious is
fairly well settled and is not particularly contentious. More problematic are
the proper boundaries of diminished capacity and
self-care.
The lions’ share of Mental Health Review Tribunal decisions on diminished capacity for self-care are correctly decided, in my view. Normally, some activity of daily living will be clearly impaired due to illness if a patient discontinues treatment. There are, however, tough cases. On several occasions the Tribunal has found a seriously diminished capacity for self-care where there is an inability, through illness, for patients to fulfil valued roles or life goals set while well. An example is the TJF case. The applicant was a wealthy 48-year-old dairy farmer with a 30-year history of schizophrenia, mostly characterized by
‘negative’ symptoms such as social isolation and
incapacity for self- care20 (as opposed to “positive”
symptoms such as delusions and persecutory ideas). His illness affected his
ability to maintain
adequate farming practices; as a result, he had come close
to losing his Fonterra supply contract due to concerns that milk
from
his farm would be unsafe.21
The first ground on which the responsible clinician maintained the compulsory
treatment order was that the applicant had led a “socially
and
intellectually impoverished life”.22 The Tribunal rejected
this, as the applicant’s situation was not sufficiently serious to
justify compulsory treatment.
19 Re TJF, above n 4, at para 26
20 Ibid, at para 2
21 Ibid, at para 30
22 Ibid, at para 2
The second ground is more compelling. The responsible clinician and
Tribunal agreed that the applicant’s sense of identity
as a dairy farmer
was a crucial component of his psychological health and self-worth.23
If he were released from compulsory treatment, his unwillingness to take
medication voluntarily and his long history of mental
illness would
prevent him from carrying on as a dairy farmer, as he would likely lose his
supply contract. The Tribunal found
that the applicant remained mentally
disordered on this ground.24
AVHM was a similar case.25 The applicant there was an
intelligent 34- year-old man with a chequered history of university study, who
lacked insight into the
nature of his illness. His decompensated mental state
left him unable to pursue his studies, but he remained focused on continuing
tertiary education, amongst other goals. AEAA similarly concerned a
trained doctor, willing but unable to practice due to a mental
disorder.26 Other close cases do not involve such heady goals: in
EJH the applicant, a frail elderly man, wanted simply to live his life
“as independently as possible.”27
The mental disorder definition is ambiguous and contentious. These
examples illustrate the difficulties faced by the Mental
Health Review
Tribunal in determining whether a patient has a seriously diminished
capacity for self-care.
B. An Interpretation of “Seriously Diminished Capacity for
Self-care”
Where the text is ambiguous, the purpose of the enactment is the
starting point for statutory interpretation.
The long title of
the MH(CAT) Act claims to “redefine the circumstances” surrounding
compulsory treatment, and
to “define [and] better protect” the
rights of compulsory patients. The latter is most helpful to interpretation,
while
all the former largely says that the MH(CAT) Act is different from that
which came before it; however, by redefining the circumstances
the
Act
23 Ibid, at para 8
24 Ibid, at para 33
25 Re AVHM, above n 7
26 Re AEAA (MHRT 08/102) 7 July 2008 at para 26
27 Re EJH (MHRT 07/140) 11 December 2007 at para
18.2
also provides them.
Considered in context, the mental disorder definition is imported into every
critical stage of assessment of a patient under Parts
1 and 2 of the MH(CAT)
Act, and during review of a patient’s compulsory status by the Tribunal
under Part 7. The clear
intention is for a patient’s condition
to be continually reconsidered in light of reassessment and any change in
circumstance.
The context of the Act is of little assistance. Parliament’s intended meaning for this phrase is not obvious from the text nor the purpose of the MH(CAT) Act, and the Parliamentary record does not assist interpretation. The (scarce) Hansard debates on the Mental Health Bill refer mainly to the poorly protected rights of patients and the risk of releasing dangerous inpatients.28 The mental disorder definition is rarely mentioned and never discussed in any depth. This lack of debate is likely a result of broad bipartisan support for the Bill.29 Despite the heavy focus of parliamentarians on patients’ rights, it would be foolish to import a civil liberties-based interpretation of the definition based on this reason alone. Many of these rights-invocations are plainly in reaction to the poor protections of the now repealed Mental Health Act
1969.
Compulsory treatment, where a patient has an abnormal state of mind causing a
seriously diminished capacity for self-care, is clearly
intended to permit that
patient to function at a higher level despite his or her mental illness. There
is an obvious overlap between
behaviours that are a danger to the
patient’s health and those that jeopardise self-care; Parliament cannot,
in providing for
both in separate paragraphs of the mental disorder definition,
be taken to have intended a doubling-up of these justifications
for
compulsory treatment. Seriously diminished capacity for self-care must
therefore include behaviours that threaten
more than just the mental or
physical health of the patient.
28 For an example of the House trying to balance civil liberties and the interest in public safety, see (1989) 502 NZPD 13605-6. The possible application of the Bill of Rights Bill to the legislation was questioned briefly at (1987) 485 NZPD 1632, but was never addressed.
29 (1992) 522 NZPD 6863; (1992) 525 NZPD 8456
1. Rights: from This Way and That
There is no disputing that the definition of mental disorder must be
interpreted by the courts and Mental Health Review Tribunal
and by the
responsible clinician in accordance with the New Zealand Bill of Rights Act
1990 (NZBORA)30 to best affirm, protect and promote the rights
contained therein.31 Any of several affirmed rights might be
infringed upon using the MH(CAT) Act depending on the nature of the compulsory
treatment
order made, but in almost every case the right to refuse medical
treatment (s 11 NZBORA) will be limited:
11 Right to refuse to undergo medical treatment
Everyone has the right to refuse to undergo any medical
treatment.
This is sometimes called the right to autonomy. Section 59(4) of the
MH(CAT) Act clearly limits this right to some extent by
saying that
treatment may be given to compulsory patients without consent, where
necessary.
The most authoritative statement of the law concerning the application of the
NZBORA is the Supreme Court case of Hansen v R.32 There the
majority held that once Parliament’s intended meaning had been
ascertained, any apparent inconsistency with the
NZBORA should be identified
and a consideration made under s 5 as to whether the limitation of
that right can be justified.
If not, the court may search for tenable
alternative meanings under s 6, which requires interpretations consistent with
the NZBORA
to be preferred.33
But what of the case where an enactment attracts no clear intended
meaning? Unlike the Hansen case, the possible meanings of
the provision in question are better represented by a spectrum than a stark
dichotomy. The
Supreme Court does provide for this alternative. The earlier
Court of Appeal decision of Moonen v Film and Literature Board
of
30 NZBORA, s 3
31 NZBORA, Long title
32 [2007] NZSC 7, [2007] 3 NZLR 1
33 Ibid, at [92] per Tipping J
Review34 concerned a provision “which involved words
that were in themselves conceptually elastic and therefore intrinsically
capable
of having a meaning which impinged more or less”35
on NZBORA- affirmed rights. In that case, the Court of Appeal said that
the first step was to find all properly open interpretations
of the
enactment in question under s 6 NZBORA, and to adopt the meaning
least infringing of the right or freedom
affected.36 Later in
Hansen, both Blanchard37 and Tipping JJ38 found
(albeit in dicta) that the Moonen approach could still apply where
no specific Parliamentary intention could be identified, while Elias CJ
expressly rejected
any form of NZBORA assessment in which s 5 was considered
first.39
The proper interpretive method under the NZBORA then, according to the appellate courts, is to determine the reasonably open interpretation of s 2 of the MH(CAT) Act that is least infringing of the right to refuse to undergo medical treatment contained in s 11
NZBORA. However, this tidy method of interpretation is likely to
remain an intellectual exercise only. The mental disorder
definition has a
long-standing, accepted and confirmed interpretation that would invariably be
applied by any lower court or tribunal
to whatever fact situations might
arise. The deeper question of interpretation would only arise on appeal
– the accepted
interpretation having already been applied to the
facts of the matter.
This broadly reflects the situation in Brooker v Police,40 a Supreme Court case handed down shortly after Hansen, which concerned the offence of disorderly behaviour under s 4(1)(a) of the Summary Offences Act
1981. As Claudia Geiringer points out, none of the three justices
forming the majority in Hansen used the agreed interpretive method in the
Brooker case.41 Blanchard J appears to explicitly
prefer an examination of whether the application of the law as it
stands is a
34 [1999] NZCA 329; [2000] 2 NZLR 9 (CA)
35 Ibid, at [93] per Tipping J
36 Ibid, at [17]
37 Hansen v R, above n 32, at [61]
38 Ibid, at [94]
39 Ibid, at [24]
40 [2007] NZSC 30, [2007] 3 NZLR 91
41 Geiringer, C. “The Principle of Legality and the Bill of Rights Act: A Critical
Examination of R v Hansen” (2008) 6 NZJPIL 59, note
144
justified limitation of the right in the particular fact
situation.42
So any examination under the NZBORA is likely to be of the
application of the mental disorder definition, and whether
or not the
limitation imposed can be justified under s 5 of that Act. Ostensibly, this
justified limitations test would be that
contained in R v Oakes43
and adopted in New Zealand in Hansen. However, Brooker has
shown that in practice the test in such a case amounts to a balancing of
interests.
In light of the alternative interpretive methods made available by the
Moonen, Hansen and Brooker cases, the proper approach to
interpretation under the NZBORA proves elusive. Most obviously the right to
refuse medical treatment,
affirmed by s 11 NZBORA, is a
primary consideration. One not yet mentioned, and closely tied to the rights
affirmed
by the NZBORA, is the common law presumption of legality whereby
legislation will only restrain liberties through clear and certain
terms. Thomas
J in R v Pora described this most concisely:44
Fundamental rights are to be taken seriously. This Court will not
accept that, in enacting legislation, Parliament has
intended to erode those
rights unless it makes its intention manifest to do so in clear and unambiguous
language.
New Zealand’s highest courts have muddied the waters of NZBORA- consistent interpretation. The proper application of ss 5 and 6
NZBORA remains unclear, despite extensive judicial discussion. Reluctantly,
I find it preferable to assess rights-consistency
with a general test
that consolidates the main aspects of both of these sections. It may be
best that that such an
ambiguous enactment should simply be given a
rights-consistent interpretation that does not permit unjustifiable limits on
those
rights. In the absence of any clear judicial direction, I adopt that
interpretive method and so examine the limitations
on the right
presented by the text and the scheme of the MH(CAT) Act.
42 Brooker v Police, above n 30, at [59]
44 R v Pora [2000] NZCA 403; [2001] 2 NZLR 37 (CA) at [120]
2. Two Limitations
Much has been made by Mental Health Review Tribunals of the right to
treatment contained in s 66 of the MH(CAT) Act:
66 Right to treatment
Every patient is entitled to medical treatment and other health care
appropriate to his or her condition.
This enactment is often cited as a counterweight to the right affirmed in s
11 NZBORA: see, for example, the application of MCM.45
This appears to be a legitimate conclusion to draw. Under s 2, a
person under compulsory treatment or assessment is a “patient”
every time a court or Review Tribunal considers their condition (and so
considers the mental disorder definition).46 Tribunals have
persistently held that a person must be treated while under a compulsory
treatment order. It follows then that treatment
must be necessary and
appropriate; unnecessary or inappropriate treatment can not constitute a
justified limitation on a right.47 Section 66 would seem to imply a
right to the best available treatment that can be given in order to prevent
relapse.
As described above, s 59(4) MH(CAT) Act is a further significant factor
limiting the s 11 right:
59 Treatment while subject to compulsory treatment order
(4) The responsible clinician shall, wherever practicable, seek to
obtain the consent of the patient to any treatment
even though that
treatment may be authorised by or under this Act without the patient’s
consent.
In combination, these sections create a significant limitation on
the right to autonomy of the person, wherever that
person is already
a patient under the MH(CAT) Act.
These sections limit the scope of the right to autonomy, but it is
not
45 Re MCM (MHRT 09/102) 9/10/2009 at para 40
46 MH(CAT) Act, ss 16, 27 and 79
47 Re CWX [1998] NZFLR 843 at 850-3
always desirable or even possible to shape the right in this way. At
every time that a responsible clinician assesses
the condition of a
person, they are a “patient” under the Act.48 However,
during the preliminary assessment examination under s 9 of the MH(CAT) Act,
the person is considered a “proposed
patient” rather than a
“patient”. At this stage, the examining medical practitioner
must determine whether
or not there are reasonable grounds to believe
that the proposed patient is mentally disordered.49 While this is
certainly a lower standard than that required before an order for compulsory
treatment is made, the assessment can still
lead to deprivation of a
person’s liberty while further assessment is undertaken, and
attendance at this examination
can be made compulsory by order of a
District Court Judge or Registrar.50 It would be strange, then, if
possible limitations on the s 11 NZBORA right were not considered by
the examining practitioner
at this stage of assessment.
The two sections are then best considered as embodying two justified limitations on the right to refuse consent to medical treatment, which apply to the mental disorder definition at every stage of assessment and treatment, regardless of whether or not a person is a “patient”. The interpretive presumption of legality requires that these sections be construed no wider than is necessary to give effect to the limitations on the right. These limitations do not completely abrogate the NZBORA right to autonomy; it would not be justified, for example, for consent to be done away with even where treatment was not appropriate to the patient’s condition. However these limitations do, in my view, act together wherever treatment is appropriate to remove the requirement of consent.
C. In Hard Cases
The vague definition of mental disorder requires a certain
interpretation. In my opinion, the question that should be asked
when assessing
mental disorder on these grounds is whether the patient’s abnormal state
of mind causes a seriously diminished
capacity to care for him or herself, and
so requires some kind of treatment in order for he or she to function
sufficiently well
according to the test outlined in
48 MH(CAT) Act, ss 11, 13 and 76
49 MH(CAT) Act, s 10(1)(b)(ii)
50 MH(CAT) Act, s 113A
re C.51 Self-care cannot, through an
NZBORA-consistent interpretation, be defined so narrowly as to only include
matters critical to the
physical and mental health of the patient; it would not
have been included in the statute as a separate justification for
compulsory treatment were this the case. Self-care is then those essential
activities of effective daily living that can be reasonably
provided by others,
or maintained with the assistance of others, as described above.
The Mental Health Review Tribunal has not ignored the NZBORA. In
TJF52 the Tribunal discussed the application of the NZBORA
to the question of self-care in some depth. They concluded that the right
to
refuse medical treatment is the “fundamental starting point” and
that this right should be balanced with the need
to receive treatment.53
I think that this interpretive method is consistent with what I
have outlined above. The right of autonomy is limited by
the MH(CAT) Act
wherever treatment is necessary, so such a balancing needs to be carried out to
determine what those necessities
of self-care are.
1. Valued Goals and Roles
The Tribunal discussed the capacity for fulfilment and
finding happiness in AVHM,54 and explained that this
will normally not be amenable to the assistance of others, except to the
extent to which obvious
deficiencies in self-care prevent fulfilment or
happiness. I think that a rights-friendly interpretation of s 2 MH(CAT) prevents
a finding of mental disorder where a person is unable to achieve valued goals
and roles and cannot be assisted in doing so by others.
Treatment is only a
justified limitation on the right of autonomy where it is necessary given the
patient’s condition. As such,
it cannot be said that a particular
treatment is necessary for self-care if no facet of self-care can be
provided for
or supported through compliance with that treatment.
The applicant in TJF55 was considered mentally
disordered due to a seriously diminished capacity to fulfil a valued role:
that of dairy farmer. I feel
that this decision cannot be legally justified
on such a narrow
51 Re C, above n 6
52 Re TJF, above n 4
53 Ibid, at para 23
54 Re AVHM, above n 7, at para 42
55 Re TJF, above n 4
ground. The applicant in that case made it quite clear that he derived
satisfaction from doing farm work by himself.56 Such work
being done by others could therefore not contribute to his sense of identity;
on the contrary, inability to work on
his farm actually detracted from
his self- worth. Given his admittedly solitary lifestyle, the only care that
others could possibly provide for him was to ensure
he remained medicated
– precisely that which conflicts with the right to autonomy, and which
the Tribunal itself was keen
to avoid in AVHM. A compulsory order to take
medication so that a person remains compliant with medication is a circular and
unattractive justification
for compulsory treatment.
A number of closely decided cases mirror the result in TJF. MCM
was decided partially on the basis that the applicant valued her roles
“as a mother, grandmother, parishioner and student.”57
In AEAA the Tribunal found that the applicant, a trained doctor,
had a seriously diminished capacity “to secure her future career in
medicine...which is central to her...sense of identity and
self-worth.”58
The decisions of the Tribunal in these three cases were not
unjust. Indeed, most would agree that a person should not lose
their chosen
fulfilling livelihood (in the case of TJF and AEAA) or important
relationships (MCM) due to mental illness. These concepts
are examples of Isaiah Berlin’s positive liberty: to act with purpose
rather than react to external causes (or, in the present case, the
uncontrollable internal forces of mental illness). I agree with
John Dawson that
these concepts are poorly embedded in New Zealand’s legal
tradition;59 as such, positive liberties are only enforceable as
far as they are specifically provided for in statute, so as to clearly
override
the negative liberty (autonomy of the person). Erratic acts done
while mentally ill cannot be considered expressions of positive
liberty, and
non-interference should not be justified by negative liberties where those acts
cause some harm to relationships or
a livelihood intrinsic to a person’s
well-being. Doing so ignores the debilitating effects of mental illness and
disregards
the value of social relationships.
56 Ibid, at para 8
57 Re MCM, above n 45, at para 47
58 Re AEAA (MHRT 08/102) 7/7/2008 at para 26
59 John Dawson “Concepts of Liberty in Mental Health Law” (2007) Otago CTO Study
<http://www.otago.ac.nz/law/otagoCTO/index.html>
Under the MH(CAT) Act, positive liberty is expressed by receiving treatment.
This can justifiably limit the right to autonomy, provided that treatment
is necessary and appropriate to the patient’s condition.
However,
this must occur within the framework provided by the MH(CAT) Act – and, as
I have said above, compulsory treatment
for a mental disorder affecting valued
goals and roles cannot be maintained based on seriously diminished capacity for
self-care.
Nigel Dunlop, a long-time convenor of the Mental Health Review Tribunal,
wrote that the overall test is one of “justification”
of
compulsory treatment, and value judgments about the impact of non-
treatment.60 By “justification”, and in the context of
his article, I take him to mean “justified limitation” of
the
right to refuse medical treatment under the NZBORA.61 This test
of justification may be the cause of strained interpretations of the
MH(CAT) Act, such as the finding that TJF
had a diminished capacity for
self-care.
I accept, as Dawson does, that a positive conception of liberty is a
relevant consideration when a person is compulsorily
treated. Intervention,
then, can be morally justified. I have discussed above how treatment can be a
justified limitation on the
right to autonomy. What remains to be established is
a legal framework for this treatment, and in most cases I think this can be
found. In TJF the Tribunal found that maintaining a sense of identity
as a dairy farmer was integral to the applicant’s psychological
and
emotional health. Why not, then, justify compulsory treatment based on an
abnormal state of mind causing a serious danger
to the health of the applicant?
“Health” in the mental disorder definition includes psychological
health.62 If the same considerations apply to assessing serious
danger as do to seriously diminished capacity,63 then the danger
to the applicant’s health was surely sufficiently serious to justify
compulsory treatment. TJF defined
himself by his profession; an inability to
continue dairy farming would have made him a fundamentally different
person.
In MCM the applicant was found to be mentally disordered on
several
60 Nigel Dunlop “Compulsory psychiatric treatment and ‘mental disorder’” [2006] NZLJ
225 at 227
61 NZBORA, s 5
62 Re IC [2001] NZHC 614; [2001] NZFLR 895 at [74]
63 Re MG, above n 5, at para 54
grounds, but if seriously diminished capacity for self-care were the sole
justification she might still be compulsorily treated under
the MH(CAT) Act. Two
of the roles M apparently valued were based on family relationships
(grandmother and mother). The ability
to form and maintain relationships
is a component of adequate self-care.64 Based on the decision of the
Tribunal, I think that the applicant’s mental illness would impair this
ability sufficiently seriously
to justify compulsory
treatment.65
The Tribunal carefully avoided this quandary in the AVHM decision. The
Tribunal made it clear that the capacity to find happiness and fulfil potential
were not a part of self-care, but that
obstacles to fulfilment, which are caused
by mental illness and amenable to the assistance of others, can be considered
if they
meet the normal definition of self- care.66 The subsequent
finding of seriously diminished capacity for self- care was based on M’s
inability to maintain an income
or assets, or relationships, so that his
goals could not be met.67 Compulsory treatment could well
have been justified on similar grounds in the AEAA case, where
the applicant was prevented from working as a doctor due to her
schizoaffective disorder.
These examples demonstrate a strained interpretation of seriously diminished
capacity for self-care. The Tribunal generally
takes a
forward-looking approach to its decisions; likelihood of relapse and the effect
of relapse are primary considerations
in determining whether patients
remain mentally disordered. Because the convenor of the Tribunal
admittedly takes the
view that compulsory treatment should be either
justified or not based on all the circumstances of the case,68 these
patients are unlikely to be released from compulsory treatment if that treatment
cannot be rationalised as due to diminished
capacity for self-care. Stated more
generally, given all the relevant circumstances it is rare that the Tribunal
will abandon a finding
that a person is mentally disordered, simply for lack of
a legal framework to support that finding.
64 324/95, above n 12
65 Re MCM, above n 45, at para 27. At least one of M’s children was prepared to trespass M from her home should she be released from compulsory treatment; another had done so in the past.
66 Ibid, at para 42
67 Ibid, at para 44
68 Dunlop, N., above n 60, at 226
Hopefully I have shown here that some alternative rationalisation is
available. Valued roles based on relationships can be
alternatively considered as an inability to form relationships
if untreated; relationships necessarily
require the participation of
other people besides the patient, and so can be considered an aspect of
self-care. Roles
based on other circumstances, such as occupation, can
be better considered as circumstances that positively contribute towards
the mental health of the applicant.
2. Giving Effect to the Patient’s Desires
Sometimes, a valued goal will not involve a great deal of talent. In
EJH, for example, the applicant had the goal of living “as
independently as possible”. This goal is not insignificant or
unimportant, but certainly is not as demanding as university study or dairy
farming, for example. The other cases detailed in the
previous section all
involve persons of high aspiration. It would be false to claim that the
Tribunal does not treat these applicants
differently from a regular patient of
middling talents.
This does not reflect a solely subjective test of diminished capacity. As I
have described above, the Tribunal has repeatedly
shied away from such
a test. In the majority of cases, diminished capacity is assessed
objectively. Special skills or specific
goals are considered differently. It is
these cases where a mixed objective/subjective approach is taken, as was
proposed by Judge
Thorburn in Re C.69
The intention of the Tribunal in such cases is not to create a higher
standard for the particularly intelligent. If it were, the
standard of care
expected of applicants would be much more obviously varied across the case
law. Rather, I think that the intention
is to give effect to the
applicant’s desires, which could not otherwise be achieved without
compulsory treatment. In EJH the applicant wished to end compulsory
treatment so as to avoid antipsychotic medication. He would have
quickly been returned
to an inpatient unit had he become non-
compliant with medication, but while medicated could be managed in a rest home,
which afforded him the greater freedom he desired. Similarly, in
TJF, AVHM, MCM and AEAA the applicants had certain
goals that could not be fulfilled in the absence of
compulsory
69 Re C, above n 6
treatment. The standard of self-care was increased in those cases based not
only on potential to achieve, but desire and potential.
The application of SMB70 was partially decided on seriously
diminished capacity for self-care. In that case the applicant had a concrete
belief that she
could regain custody of her children by repeatedly appealing
the matter to the Privy Council and the United Nations Human Rights
Committee. B
had previously failed in both forums. One consideration the Tribunal had in
mind was that the Applicant’s
intense desire to travel overseas and
appeal the matter would actually take her away from her children, as she would
be in a different
country and have no chance of legal success.71 The
patient’s desire to have her children returned to her custody was
therefore best enhanced by sustaining compulsory treatment
(although there is no
indication that the Tribunal decided the application on this matter).
3. The Potential for Homelessness
As in the case of EJH, often a particular accommodation will only be
maintained as long as the applicant is in good mental health. When mental
health
deteriorates, the same conditions cannot be sustained and the patient
loses their accommodation. There is potential then
for patients to become
homeless if improperly released from compulsory treatment.
Sometimes such a case is assessed as a deficit of self-care. This
is generally the case when an applicant wishes
to leave a care
facility without having alternative care plans. In the case of FS,72
for example, the elderly applicant lived in a rest home because her
husband could not care for her at home. She would leave the
home if released
from compulsory treatment, due to her grandiose schemes for solving world
problems. This can be characterised as
an inability to accept care due to an
abnormal state of mind.
Other cases involve an unwillingness to receive treatment,
while
70 Re SMB (MHRT 07/151) 20 March 2007
71 Ibid, at para 52
72 Re FS (NRT 563/98) 20 March 1998
intending to remain in care. The facts of FLW73 and
DBF74 are broadly similar. In each case, an elderly
applicant cared for in a rest home sought release from compulsory
treatment,
but wished to remain in care at the same facility. This was
simply not possible: the applicants would become too difficult
to manage
in the community if their conditions went untreated, which would force
a move into inpatient care. These decisions
focused on the availability of a
less intrusive form of treatment. Rest home care is much preferable to inpatient
care at a hospital.
The pharmaceutical treatment involved might remain
the same, but at least the therapy milieu is more agreeable.
D. Victoria: A Comparison
In Victoria, the criteria for compulsory treatment are contained in s 8(1)
of the Mental Health Act 1986 (the Victorian MHA).
8 Criteria for involuntary treatment
(1) The criteria for the involuntary treatment of a person under this Act are that-
(a) the person appears to be mentally ill; and
(b) the person's mental illness requires immediate treatment and that treatment can be obtained by the person being subject to an involuntary treatment order; and
(c) because of the person's mental illness, involuntary treatment of the person is necessary for his or her health or safety (whether to prevent a deterioration in the person's physical or mental condition or otherwise) or for the protection of members of the public; and
(d) the person has refused or is unable to consent to the necessary treatment for the mental illness; and
(e) the person cannot receive adequate treatment for the mental
illness in a manner less restrictive of his or her freedom
of decision and
action.
Section 8(1)(c) is broadly equivalent to the second limb of the mental
disorder definition contained in s 2(1) of the MH(CAT) Act.
The main difference
between these provisions is the absence, in the Victorian
73 Re FLW (MHRT 07/073) 19 July 2007
74 Re DBF (MHRT 08/088) 7 November 2008
statute, of seriously diminished capacity for self-care (or equivalent) as a
justification for compulsory treatment.
Some aspects of self-care, such as nutrition and housing, could easily be
considered as harmful to the health of a person where
they are not
present. In AW,75 for example, the patient had been homeless
over a long period; this was rightly considered harmful to his physical health.
However,
the absence of a specific provision for when diminished self- care
justifies compulsory treatment might indicate that
the more complex
matters of self-care, such as the maintenance of beneficial relationships, are
not good reasons for depriving a
patient of his or her liberty in that
jurisdiction. Other Australian jurisdictions had, at the time of enactment
of the
Victorian MHA, criteria for compulsory treatment that explicitly
incorporated matters of self-care.76 Since the enactment of the
Victorian MHA, however, states have taken a still narrower approach. In
Queensland77 and in the Australian Capital Territory,78
for example, the criteria for compulsory treatment conspicuously lack any
reference to the health of the patient; the phrase “mental
or physical
deterioration” is preferred. This may indicate that in Victoria health is
an expansive concept including “complete
physical, mental and social
well-being”.79
The Victorian Mental Health Review Board initially endorsed the
expansive view of health. In the review of BC,80 the
Board gave a reading of “health” in s 8(1)(c) that included the
more complex matters normally considered as a
part of self-care in New
Zealand and other jurisdictions. Compulsory treatment could be justified
if:
there is a real risk that, without treatment, the
behavioural manifestations of the mental illness will be such
as to result
in the person’s isolation for [sic] the community in which he or she
lives,
75 Re AW (1991) 1 MHRBD (Vic) 414
76 See for example the NSW Mental Health Act 1958, s 18. A mentally ill person is
defined partly as one “incapable of managing himself or his affairs”.
77 Mental Health Act 2000 (Qld), s 14
78 Mental Health (Treatment and Care) Act 1994 (ACT), s 28
79 Preamble to the Constitution of the World Health Organization as adopted by the
International Health Conference, New York, 19-22 June, 1946
80 Re BC (1987) 1 MHRBD (Vic) 26
interacts and is sustained.81
Presumably the Board intended to say “from” rather than “for” where I
have indicated.
This reasoning was taken up in later decisions. In CW82
the applicant had caused damage to his family relationships through his
vociferous opposition to the church attended by his wife
and children. He felt
that all the family should worship in one church. Otherwise, W functioned
perfectly normally, and had
no delusional beliefs. He was not
considered a risk to the safety of others, nor to his own safety or
physical
health. His continued detention was justified entirely on the
basis of the continuing damage to his familial relationships.83 This
trend was continued in LR, where the Board equates “social
stability and mental health”. 84
A differently constituted Board rejected this reasoning in
HL.85 That Board preferred to use social isolation as an
indicator of deterioration in physical or mental health, rather than
a condition that would justify compulsory treatment.86 L was
a middle-aged woman with fixed delusional religious beliefs, who thought
that the Virgin Mary had cured her diabetes.
L’s social isolation was used
as evidence that her physical and mental condition might deteriorate were
she not subject
to compulsory treatment. This rejection of social
well-being as a component of health may indicate an overstepping
of the
statutory language by earlier tribunals. The adoption of more specific
statutory language in other Australian states certainly
indicates an
unwillingness to examine relationships as evidence of mental
illness requiring treatment in those
jurisdictions. The New Zealand
Mental Health Review Tribunal confines its inquiry to the physical and mental
aspects of health;
this narrow interpretation seems the best approach to take in
a field where rights are normally at issue, in the absence
of wider
legislative criteria.
81 Ibid, at 29
82 Re CW (1993) 2 MHRBD (Vic) 64
83 Ibid, at 73-4
84 Re LR (No. 2) (1995) 2 MHRBD (Vic) 214 at 217
85 Re HL (1997) 2 MHRBD (Vic) 485
86 Ibid, at 499
Conclusion
The Mental Health Review Tribunal walks a fine line between paternalism and ensuring that patients receive necessary and appropriate treatment. Generally the Tribunal comes to the right decision, albeit sometimes for flawed reasons. I have acknowledged that the outcomes of Tribunal hearings would probably not change if certain lines of reasoning were not available – but nor should they change in most cases. However it is important, both for the satisfaction of the applicant and the avoidance of fruitless appeals, that such decisions are legitimately reasoned within the law. This requires an interpretation of the mental disorder definition that reflects the purpose of the MH(CAT) Act, as well as the relevant rights and interests of patients. Limitation of these rights can only be justified where treatment is necessary for the fulfilment of the second limb of the mental disorder definition.
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/NZLawStuJl/2010/5.html