![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
New Zealand Law Students Journal |
Last Updated: 9 August 2012
THE CASE FOR CLIFF-TOP DUTIES
CLAIRE
BRIGHTON*
Introduction
The common law has long rejected the notion of a general duty to rescue. As
Lord Keith famously explained, should a man see another
about to walk off a
cliff-top there would be no legal duty to shout a warning or
intervene.[1] This rejection reflects
not only the law’s commitment to maintaining the distinction between moral
and legal duties, but also
its strict adherence to the principled construction
of positive obligations. The two greatest obstacles to such a duty are therefore
the general rule relating to nonfeasance and the issue of causation. While the
courts remain strong advocates of the general rule
against finding positive
duties, the growing number of exceptions suggest a gradual erosion of its
austerity. These obstacles and
the rationale behind them are discussed in the
first section of this dissertation. Moving on from these issues, the second
section
sets out the argument for a limited duty to rescue based upon an
assumption of responsibility coupled with general reliance or dependence,
as
proposed by James Edelman and Nathalie Gray. The authors focus on the special
role that certain professionals hold within society
and the expectations that
society consequently places upon then in relation to effecting rescue. I argue
that while this framework
is compelling, it is also open to critique, most
crucially in relation to their evaluation of the doctrine of general reliance.
In
light of the implications of a duty that necessarily arises between
strangers, it is imperative that the doctrine be correctly applied.
The final
part of this dissertation therefore endeavours to present a logical
justification for how the doctrine might be applied
within the framework of the
proposed duty so as to sufficiently justify an exception to the general rule
against positive obligations.
I.
A. The Current Approach and the
Distinction between Moral and Legal Duties
There is currently no general common law duty to aid a person in peril, regardless of the ease of rescue or the severity of the consequences. Thus the courts have held that there was no duty for a expert swimmer to rescue an intoxicated party from drowning,[2] for a bystander to come to assist a stranger bleeding to death,[3] or for a physician to answer the call of one who is dying and might be saved.[4] While in such circumstances there may be a moral duty to act, the common law has steadfastly held that moral duties, while compelling, are not legally enforceable. The distinction between moral and legal duties is founded on two connected assertions. First, that morality is an internal phenomenon and decisions to act altruistically ought therefore to be matters of free choice.[5] As Kant asserts ‘law cannot make a person virtuous’.[6] Secondly, the translation of morality directly into law faces practical difficulty in light of its inherently subjective nature. In Heyman’s words: [7]
[as] morality is rooted in the inner subjectivity of the individual...the moral duty to aid others is too indefinite for legal enforcement. Although morality enjoins one to promote the well-being of others in general, it does not specify to whom this duty is owed or how much must be done to satisfy it. Therefore, insofar as the obligation to aid others is a moral one, it may not be enforced by positive law.
Accepting however that much of the law is founded upon notions of moral
right and wrong, and that the lines between moral and legal
wrongs inevitably
overlap, the courts have imposed a number of rules pertaining to the finding of
a legal duty.[8]
When a
proposed novel duty in negligence arises “one should ask not whether it is
covered by authority but whether recognised
principles apply to
it”.[9] This approach might be
demonstrated by reference to Lord Atkin’s interpretation of the moral and
Biblical rule that one is
to love thy neighbour. In the Biblical text, when
posed with the question “who is my neighbour?” Jesus responded by
telling
the story of a man lying bleeding on the side of the road. Three
strangers walked past. While two simply ignored the injured man,
the third, a
Samaritan,[10] came to his
rescue.[11] The story suggests that
all persons are morally obliged to aid a fellow human-being in peril. Within the
legal context however, Lord
Atkin stated in Donoghue v Stevenson that
“the rule that you are to love your neighbour, becomes in law, you must
not injure your neighbour”.
[12] Thus, while one is obligated to not
harm another there is no general legal duty to confer a benefit. Furthermore,
when asked who
then is one’s neighbour? Lord Atkin pointed toward the
principles of foreseeability, proximity and causation, stating that
such a duty
was owed only to:[13]
Persons who are so closely and directly affected by my act that I ought reasonably to have them in contemplation as being so affected when I am directing my mind to the acts or omissions which are called in question.
His Lordship’s statement has since been developed by the courts
into a number of tests under which the scope and existence of
a duty is
determined in reference to established legal principles, furnished by, but not
founded on, considerations of what is moral
or ‘fair, just and
reasonable’.[14] Consequently,
under the common law the first two strangers in the Biblical parable would have
incurred no liability.[15] There are
two major obstacles to the finding of a general duty to rescue under these
current duty tests. First, the law’s distinction
between misfeasance and
nonfeasance, and second, the requirement of a causative connection between the
party’s own behaviour
and the loss suffered by reference to the principle
of proximity. This discussion now turns to an examination of these two points.
1. Misfeasance and Nonfeasance
As Bohlen states “There is no distinction more deeply rooted in the
common law and more fundamental than that between misfeasance
and
nonfeasance”.[16] While a
party will be liable for a wrongful act that renders another positively worse
off, they will generally not be liable for
merely declining to act so as to
confer a benefit. The justification for this approach lies in the law’s
jealous protection
of personal autonomy and the theory of the social
contract.[17]
Social
contract theory holds that in submitting to the governance of the state, an
individual is granted the state’s protection
and ‘the assurance that
he will be free to realise his life
plans’.[18] In order to effect
this protection, the state requires that, all citizens, in return, consent to
not actively interfere with the
rights of others. The law generally imposes
liability only where an individual acts contrary to this requirement, not when
they simply
decline to advance the interests of others, as that would constitute
a more serious interference with their
liberty.[19] Here the social
contract represents a fine balance between protection, right, and autonomy. It
is the role of the state, not the
individual, to afford protection to other
citizens. However, the rules and laws that are imposed in order to deter and
punish individuals
for unduly interfering with the rights of others in turn
limit all citizens’ autonomous rights. The general rule relating to
nonfeasance therefore represents one mechanism by which the balance between the
rights of another and the rights of an individual
are set.
Two issues
might be raised regarding a general duty to rescue. First, that the imposition
of such a duty effectively renders the right
of an individual to make autonomous
decisions subservient to the needs of others in peril. This would distort the
balance between
protection and autonomy, and is arguably beyond the justifiable
scope of the law. Secondly, because such a duty necessarily contemplates
circumstances involving strangers, it would constitute a unilateral limitation
on the rights of the individual on whom it is imposed.
Indeed Ripstein argues
that the individual’s responsibility not to interfere with the rights of
others includes the subsidiary
requirement that one must avoid displacing the
costs of one’s choices onto
others.[20] Thus ‘equal
freedom can also be described as the idea that one person’s liberty will
not be limited unilaterally by another’s
vulnerability, nor one
person’s security limited unilaterally by another’s
choices’.[21] Indeed according
to early natural right theorists such as Locke the correct function of law is to
protect individual rights, not
to impose upon individuals affirmative duties
that act to disproportionately fetter their autonomy.
[22]
2. Causation, Proximity and Exceptions to the General
Rule
The principle of causation is fundamental to the establishment of liability
for negligence. Generally, establishing causation requires
that the harm
suffered be positively caused by a defendant’s conduct. In other words it
must be shown that ‘but for’
D’s conduct, P would not have
suffered loss. The obstacle presented by the requirement of the causative link
is therefore closely
connected to that presented by the rule relating to
nonfeasance. Indeed one might question how an individual’s failure to act
could be seen as a legal cause of loss to another. The answer stems from Lord
Atkin’s reference to both acts and omissions
in
Donoghue,[23] in light of
which the courts have held that where there is a positive duty of care, a
failure to fulfil that duty is capable of being
the active cause of loss to
another. However, the formulation of a positive duty, so as to constitute an
exception to the general
rule, is necessarily more complex than the formulation
of a negative one. In developing a body of exceptions, the courts have adopted
a
somewhat piece-meal approach. The difficulty in finding any obvious overarching
rationale for the increasing list of exceptions
reflects this inherent
complexity.
Non-exhaustively, the courts have found positive duties
where: a party has contributed to the risk of the harm eventuating, such as
where a bar manager supplied alcohol to a patron who later crashed while
intoxicated;[24] where there is a
special relationship between the parties, such as the paternalistic relationship
between a parent and child,[25] or
the relationship of control between a prisoner and
gaoler;[26] where there has been an
assumption of responsibility by the defendant coupled with reliance on the part
of the plaintiff, such as
a military base that organised return transport for
soldiers from an event where excessive alcohol consumption was
expected;[27] or where a party has
control over property that poses a risk to others; such as the owner of a
cattle-station who failed to put out
a fire that then spread to neighbouring
property.[28]
As stated,
there is no obvious general principle linking these categories. However, in all
cases there is some direct or indirect
connection or relationship of proximity
between the parties, which at the very least might be distinguished from those
instances
of pure nonfeasance involving mere strangers. As explained in Prosser
and Keeton on Torts:[29]
The question appears to be essentially one of whether the defendant has gone so far in what he has actually done, and has gotten himself into such a relation with the plaintiff, that he has begun to affect the interests of the plaintiff adversely, as distinguished from merely failing to confer a benefit on him.
In such circumstances it is both by virtue of this proximate connection
to the other party, and only to the extent determined by the
nature of that
relationship, that the law justifies the prioritisation of another’s right
to protection over the individual’s
right to autonomy.
In rescuer
cases, a mere stranger (A) who happens to witness another (B) in peril is not
responsible for the creation of any risk
to B and there is no special
relationship which would place an affirmative duty on A so that the failure to
carry it out could be
seen to cause the
injury.[30] Indeed, as B’s
predicament arose entirely independently of A, the only arguable basis for a
duty is that of means and circumstantial
proximity. It is clear however, that
this alone is not sufficient to give rise to a positive duty.
[31] There are a number of good policy
reasons for this. Firstly, unlike instances where there is a previous
relationship, A would have
no ability to take steps to prevent or decrease the
risk of B finding himself in that position of
peril.[32] Secondly, as any duty to
rescue would be imposed purely by B’s plight, such a duty stands in clear
conflict with both the
rule that persons cannot unilaterally impose duties on
other,[33] and the requirement that
duties be founded on notions of what is fair, just and
reasonable.[34] Finally, on a more
practical level there is no rational justification for singling out or
‘picking’ A over any other
stranger.[35] In Lord Reid’s
words: ‘where a person has done nothing to put himself in any relationship
with another person in distress...mere
accidental propinquity does not require
him to go to that person’s
assistance’.[36]
There
is therefore no foundation on which the law can justify upsetting the
aforementioned balance between autonomy and right by imposing
a general duty to
rescue. The current discussion does not seek to defend such a duty, but rather
presents a more limited duty which
rests somewhere between the rejected general
duty and the accepted exceptions. It is to this more limited duty that the
discussion
now turns.
II.
A. Lowns v Woods – A good place to start?
Before
addressing the specific perimeters of the proposed duty there is one case worth
noting. In Lowns v Woods[37]
the New South Wales Court of Appeal upheld the finding of a duty to rescue on
the part of a doctor who failed to respond to a request
to attend a 10 year old
boy having an epileptic fit nearby. As a result of this failure the boy did not
receive treatment in time,
suffered major brain damage and consequently became
permanently disabled. The Court upheld the finding of a positive duty,
notwithstanding
the fact that there was no previous relationship. The judgments
presented in both the initial Court and on appeal have been heavily
criticised
for failing to appropriately address the issues of nonfeasance and
causation.[38] It would appear that
rather than addressing the difficulties associated with establishing a positive
as opposed to negative duty,
the judges misused policy as a justification for
the finding of proximity, thus failing to acknowledge the distinction between
moral
and legal duties.[39] This
dissertation argues however that the facts of the case demonstrate exactly the
sort of situation in which a limited duty to
rescue ought to apply. As the
arguments presented in Lowns fail to sufficiently address the relevant
issues, this discussion now turns to an academic proposal that seeks to do
exactly that.
1. Edelman and Gray: A proposed Limited Duty to
Rescue
In their article ‘Developing the law of Omission: a Common Law Duty to
Rescue’,[40] Gray and Edelman
propose a limited duty to rescue based upon the dual components of assumption of
responsibility and reliance or
dependence. They assert that the mistake that the
(lack of) causation/proximity type argument makes is in assuming that, for the
purposes of rescue, all bystanders are in the same position in relation to the
person in peril. They suggest that ‘the existence of a special
relationship should not merely be determined by reference to the individual
rescuer
and victim but by having regard to the societal relationships that exist
between classes of potential rescuers and the victims they
would be capable of
assisting’.[41] The
author’s tentatively base their proposed duty on the doctrine of general
reliance, which acts to relax the specificity
required for both elements of
assumption and reliance, thus allowing it to be applied to circumstances
involving complete strangers.
Noting a number of uncertainties surrounding the
validity of the doctrine, Edelman and Gray present a piecemeal justification for
its application within their proposed duty. Applied to the facts of Lowns
the authors argue that by voluntarily holding himself out to be a practising
medical practitioner Dr Lowns entered a special relationship
with the epileptic
boy characterised by an assumption of responsibility on the part of Dr Lowns and
vulnerability and dependence
on the part of the boy. Consequently Dr Lowns owed
a positive duty of care to the boy which he failed to fulfil, thus causing his
injury.[42]
(a) Elements of Proximity - Assumption of
Responsibility and Reliance
Ever since the House of Lords decision in Hedley
Byrne,[43] the concept of an
assumption of responsibility, coupled with reliance on the part of another party
have been regular features of
the determination of a duty of care. Here, whether
in relation to a certain activity or in relation to an undertaking that affects
the plaintiff, responsibility is seen as some kind of choice made and acted upon
by the parties. One party consciously takes on something
while another
consciously relies upon that.[44]
Proximity in such cases is thus ‘understood as being governed on both
sides by perception and
intention’.[45] The
application of this dual construction of proximity has been varied, and at times
the courts have found sufficient proximity in
circumstances where the reliance
element is weaker, or indeed absent altogether. However, it is clear that in all
constructions save
one, the courts have held that it is crucial that there be a
sufficient degree of specificity as to who the elements are directed
at. The one
exception, which also features in Edelman and Gray’s proposed duty, is the
somewhat contentious doctrine of general
reliance established in The Council
of the Shire of Suntherland v
Heyman.[46]
(i) Doctrine of General Reliance
The reliance element of the assumption/reliance construction of proximity
normally arises out of a previous relationship, or alternately,
in a very
limited group of cases, by way of a previous relationship by proxy, such as the
relationship between a legatee of a solicitor’s
client and that
solicitor.[47] In such cases the
imposition of liability for the loss suffered is logically justified because the
defendant has had the opportunity
to take precautions to decrease the likelihood
that harm would come to the
plaintiff.[48] As stated in
Barrett v Ministry of Defence ‘The characteristic which
distinguishes those relationships is reliance expressed or implied in the
relationship which the party to whom the duty is owed is entitled to place
on the other party to make provision for his
safety’.[49]
Under the
doctrine of general reliance however, this requirement of a prior relationship,
or indeed any form of specificity as to
whom an assumption of responsibility or
reliance is directed at is significantly relaxed. Mason J presented the doctrine
in the Australian
case of Sutherland stating that:
[50]
There will be cases in which the plaintiff's reasonable reliance will arise out of a general dependence on an authority's performance of its function with due care...This situation generates on one side (the individual) a general expectation that the power will be exercised and on the other side (the authority) a realisation that there is a general reliance or dependence on its exercise of the power.
His Lordship further discussed the basis of the concept stating:
[51]
Reliance or dependence in this sense is in general the product of the grant (and exercise) of powers designed to prevent or minimise a risk of personal injury or disability, recognised by the legislature as being of such magnitude or complexity that individuals cannot, or may not, take adequate steps for their own protection.
Similarly, in Parramatta City Council v Lutz
[52] McHugh J stated
that the doctrine was justified by the failure of the traditional categories to
give protection to individual members
of the community from harm. Thus, the
normal conscious assumption and reliance is, in essence, replaced by implied
assumption and
implied reliance on the basis of a legislative power or duty.
Under Edelman and Gray’s proposed construction of proximity,
rather than being the product of a legislative power general reliance
arises out
of the reasonable expectation that persons who constitute a particular class
performing a specific role within society
will act according to their skills and
powers. They argue that in the same way that parties are dependent on public
bodies to exercise
statutory functions, so too are individuals reliant on
specific skilled groups within society to assist in times of peril. It would
also logically follow that such persons would be aware of those expectations and
the extent to which citizens depend upon the exercise
of their skills in times
of emergency.[53]
The
general reliance doctrine has been adopted by some courts in
Australia[54] and New
Zealand.[55] It was however,
rejected by a 3/2 majority of the High Court of Australia in Pyrenees v
Day.[56] While Edelman and Gray
acknowledge the difficulty posed by Pyrenees, they argue that this merely
renders the approach difficult as a unitary
test.[57] They assert that where
coupled with additional proximity factors the doctrine may provide a powerful
argument for proximity.
(ii) Assumption of Responsibility and Dependence –
the Additional Proximity Factors
The concept of an assumption of responsibility first appeared within the law
of negligence in the case of Hedley Byrne v Heller. In his
judgment Lord Devlin described such an assumption as ‘a responsibility
that is voluntarily accepted or undertaken, either
generally where a general
relationship, such as that of solicitor and client or banker and customer, is
created, or specifically
in relation to a particular
transaction.’[58] If
established, such an assumption was capable of giving rise to a duty of care.
Under Edelman and Gray’s proposal, every ‘class of
professional person which has rescue as an aspect of its work, and
which carries
on its duties in accordance with standards of conduct or specialised
training,’ has by taking up that position
assumed responsibility for
certain relevant rescue situations should they
arise.[59] This would apply notably
to medical practitioners and public rescue bodies such as fire-fighters and
ambulance officers.[60] The finding
of such an assumption is founded on the fact that such parties hold themselves
out as being capable of rescuing, and
from the realisation that lay persons in
peril would not have the skills or ability to aid
themselves.[61] Taking the example
of a doctor, Edelman and Gray note both Dr Lowns’ acceptance in
Lowns that, under the ordinary standards of a medical practitioner, he
would have been obliged to respond, and that the Medical Practitioners Act
sets out a professional obligation to assist those in need of urgent
attention.[62] They argue
that while these factors are neither necessary nor sufficient in themselves to
establish a duty of care, they do lend
support to the argument that doctors are,
or could reasonably be expected to be, aware that in entering the profession
they are assuming
responsibilities beyond those that they have specifically
contracted for. Similar legislation and general understandings of what
the role
entails might be noted in regards to other professional rescuers. However, as
with the medical example, such factors are
merely required to lend support to
the argument.
Edelman and Gray then turn to a number of cases where an
assumption of responsibility has been associated with the concept of induced
dependence or vulnerability rather than reliance in a specific sense. In
Hawkins v Clayton[63] a
solicitor was held liable for the loss suffered by a deceased client’s
estate as a result of the solicitor failing to inform
the executor of the
existence of a will.[64] In his
judgment Deane J held that there was a sufficient relationship of reliance and
assumption between the solicitor and the deceased
client to hold the solicitor
liable for foreseeable loss to the estate even where there was no actual
reliance by the estate’s
representative.[65] Alternately,
Gaudron J held that sufficient proximity was based on the executor’s
‘reasonable expectation’ of disclosure
regardless of the fact that
he had no knowledge of the existence of either the solicitor or the will and
thus could not have relied
on the solicitor in the specific
sense.[66]
Edelman and Gray
assert that this concept of ‘reasonable expectation’ in the absence
of specific reliance might be used
to justify a duty based upon an expectation
that a certain class of persons would act according to their skills and powers
once they
have assumed responsibility for doing
so.[67] The authors argue that it is
difficult to distinguish between a non-specific reliance on a class of persons
who hold themselves out
to have certain skills (such as solicitors), and general
reliance in a class that claim that they will perform a certain role in
society
(such as rescue professionals).[68]
Furthermore, persons in need of rescue are certainly vulnerable in the sense
that they are necessarily incapable of assisting themselves.
[69]
The authors conclude that an
assumption of responsibility by one class of persons over a situation coupled
with dependence on the
part of another class (or the existence of a reasonable
expectation as to how the former will act) is sufficient to create an overriding
relationship of proximity upon which a duty to rescue might be found. In
addition, they claim that such a construction of proximity
is really only a
one-step extension of the category of exceptions covering relationships where
there has been an assertion of control
over the
plaintiff.[70] They argue that where
there is dependence, an assertion of control is
expected.[71]
2. Critique and an Alternate Argument
Two significant objections might be raised to Edelman and Gray’s
proximity argument. While these objections are not fatal to
the duty proposed,
they do render unsatisfactory the authors’ justification for their
construction of proximity. This part
of the discussion seeks to identify and
address these objections and propose and justify a slightly altered argument for
proximity.
(a) Pyrenees – Rejection of the
Doctrine
The first objection to Edelman and Gray’s argument relates to the
majority’s rejection of the doctrine of general reliance
in
Pyrenees.[72] While the
authors acknowledge that Pyrenees is problematic, they assert that the
judgment merely renders the doctrine incapable of being utilised as a unitary
test, concluding
that when coupled with other elements it is still strongly
arguable. This analysis is both insufficient in that it fails to address
the
arguments raised by the majority and incorrect in that the ‘additional
elements’ presented by the authors are not
sufficient to fulfil the
proximity requirement needed to justify an exception to the rule of nonfeasance.
Pyrenees concerned the existence of a common law duty of care
owed by a council to subsequent occupiers of a property it had inspected. In
1988 the Pyrenees Shire Council had inspected a chimney and discovered that it
was not safe to use. The Council wrote to the occupier
of the premises warning
that it was not safe to be used until it was repaired. The repairs were not
carried out, and the Council
made no further enquiries to see if it had been
repaired or ensure that it was not in use. In early 1990 the lease to the
premises
was assigned to the Plaintiffs who were unaware of the letter or the
danger. In mid-1990 a fire broke-out destroying the premises
and damaging
adjoining premises. The High Court of Australia held that the Council owed a
statutory duty to the Plaintiffs, but rejected
the doctrine of general reliance
and held that the doctrine had no part to play in the finding of the
duty.[73]
Each of the three
majority judges in Pyrenees had slightly different reasons for rejecting
the doctrine. Gummow J rejected it on the basis that as there was no
conscious reliance actually placed on the defendant, the doctrine represented
the creation of a new legal fiction, something the law approached with
hostility. He concluded that liability should not be imposed
in terms that do
not command an intellectual assent or refer liability directly to basal
principle.[74] Alternately, Brennan
J noted the practical and undesirable implication of making general community
expectations the touchstone of
liability. Were legislative powers and grants to
be found capable of attracting common law damages, the appropriate criterion
would
be legislative intention.[75]
Kirby J took a slightly different approach, first rejecting the doctrine as a
legal fiction but then suggesting that the factors
that had been thought to
establish the doctrine might be viewed as “proximity factors” going
to the establishment of
the normal
requirement.[76] It is perhaps this
position that led Edelman and Gray to the conclusion that Pyreness posed
no issue to the doctrine when combined with other elements. However, one might
point out that there is nothing in Kirby J’s
statements to imply that by
allowing factors thought to give rise to the doctrine to be counted as proximity
factors, the standard
of proximity would be relaxed. In fact, Kirby J cited Lord
Hoffman’s judgment in Stovin v Wise specifically criticising the
doctrine for appearing to discard the requirement that a plaintiff specifically
rely upon the defendant.[77] It is
therefore clear that under the majority’s judgment, any combination of
proximity factors will still have to demonstrate
a sufficient degree of
proximity to justify an exception to the rule against nonfeasance, whether or
not it includes those associated
with general reliance.
Edelman and
Gray’s discussion of the various additional elements that might be
combined with the doctrine to produce a convincing
argument for proximity
becomes confused relatively quickly. They assert that the doctrine is arguable
when coupled with both an assumption
of responsibility on the part of
professional persons assuming certain roles within society, and dependence or
‘general expectations
of the community’ as to the fulfilment of
those roles. However, the idea of “combining” these elements with
the
doctrine of general reliance is difficult to conceive considering that these
elements themselves would appear to be the only arguable
factors that could have
been seen to establish the two parts of the doctrine of general reliance in the
first place. In reality there
is no “combining,” as these were not
“additional elements”. Rather there is simply an argument asserting
a very unspecific assumption on the part of certain person with a very
unspecific reliance or dependence on the part of society.
Having rejected the
assertion that the doctrine of general reliance somehow provides some additional
argument for proximity over
and above the proximity factors actually identified,
the question becomes whether the assumption and dependence factors proposed
are
capable of providing a sufficient argument for proximity.
In relation to
the first factor proposed, it is submitted that an assumption of responsibility
by professional parties to any person
needing rescue in circumstances where that
party is capable of carrying it out essentially amounts to an assumption of
responsibility
to the whole world. While the concept of an assumption has been
applied in a number of different
forms[78] they have always involved
a specific assumption for a specific activity in relation to a specific group of
persons. The concept that
a duty cannot be owed to the world can be seen in a
number of decisions.[79] In
Caparo, Lord Bridge stated in that the requirement of specificity acted
to prevent ‘liability in an indeterminate amount for an indeterminate
time
to an indeterminate
class’.[80] As Todd states:
[81]
Merely assuming an office or status and having the ability to help is not likely to be enough...there must at least be an assumption of responsibility for, and close control over, a particular activity in relation to a particular person or class before a duty might come to be recognised.
Accepting that an assumption of responsibility indicates proximity, the
ability of the proximity requirement to act as a ‘limit[ing]
or control
mechanism’ for liability[82]
would arguably be defeated if a party could be held to have assumed
responsibility to all persons. The proposed assumption of responsibility
is
therefore incapable of providing a sufficient argument for proximity.
In
relation to the second proposed proximity factor it is submitted that
non-specific reliance or dependence had only ever been accepted
in a very
limited category of cases where there has been some form of specific assumption
or control justifying the imposition of
liability. Edelman and Gray point to the
case of Hawkins[83]
as providing support for their assertion that dependence alone constitutes
a valid proximity factor. While the authors acknowledge
that the judgments began
by noting that proximity existed between the deceased and the solicitor, they
fail to acknowledge the relevance
of this in relation to other parties.
Furthermore, both Gauldron and Deane JJ identified the relationship of control
between the
executor and the solicitor by way of the solicitor’s
assumption of control over the deceased’s will and thus his testamentary
intentions.[84] Here the solicitor
had made a conscious undertaking toward the deceased specifically, which, when
coupled with dependence, reliance
or indeed ‘general expectations’,
could be extended to those parties foreseeably affected by
it.[85] Such a specific undertaking
or assumption is significant in justifying an exception both because it means
that the duty in question
was not unilaterally imposed, and because, on the
basis of this prior relationship, the defendant was capable of preventing or
alleviating
the risk placed upon the plaintiff. A similar objection might be
raised to the authors’ assertion that their construction of
proximity is
merely one-step beyond the category of control. At the core of the rationale for
allowing an exception where there is
a relationship of control is the fact that
once control has been exerted the party exerting it is capable of preventing or
alleviating
risk.[86] Thus, the
solicitor had the ability to prevent any loss to the estate simply by informing
the executor of the will. Where however,
as the authors propose, there is merely
the potential or the expectation of an exertion of control this fundamental
characteristic
is lacking. It might be merely one-step, but that one-step is
fundamental. In sum, the softening of the reliance requirement in Hawkins
was based on the specific undertaking and control held by the defendant, the
fact that those affected were readily ascertainable,
and the unavoidable
vulnerability of the plaintiff.[87]
Considering that Edelman and Gray’s proposed argument lacks the key
elements of control and specific undertaking, Hawkins can provide little
support. Indeed the courts have demonstrated an unwillingness to apply the
exception where all these elements
are not
present.[88]
Summing up the
first objection: Edelman and Gray’s failure to adequately deal with the
rejection of the doctrine as a unitary
test meant that any proposal they
presented necessarily required a closer connection (proximity) between the
parties than the non-specific
elements provided by the doctrine. In light of the
fact that no additional proximity factors connecting a rescuee and rescuer would
be present in situations to which the duty would apply, their argument was
necessarily based simply on a deemed assumption of responsibility
to the world
and non-specific reliance or general expectations. It is submitted that if
specificity is unavailable then the only
possible way to render the proposed
duty arguable is to address the issues raised in Pyrenees and defend the
doctrine in its unitary form. This was, I believe, successfully done by the
minority judges.
In his dissent Toohey J stressed that the
doctrine of general reliance is only a fiction in the sense that it is not
actual reliance. He further
pointed out that negligence is not a stranger to
legal fictions.[89] Indeed the
concept of an assumption of responsibility is itself essentially a legal
fiction, as, in reality tort obligations are
imposed not
assumed.[90] The question therefore
is whether such a “fiction” is desirable in light of the practical
dangers of making general community
expectations the touchstone of liability.
Here McHugh J asserted in his dissent that if the limitations of the doctrine
are properly
understood then this danger is overstated. The doctrine applies
only in cases where it can be established that individuals could
not protect
themselves and thus were entirely dependent on the public body and where that
body knew of the danger of not exercising
their powers. Furthermore, he noted
that the doctrine would not lead to liability merely by reason of a failure to
carry out a power,
as this would depend on all the circumstances in the case
including competing demands on the body in question and terms of the statutory
power.[91] In sum, as the law is not
adverse to legal fictions, this alone is not reason enough to reject the
doctrine. Considering the practical
limitations that might be applied to curtail
the duty, it is arguable that the value in the protection that the doctrine
provides
to those members of the public who are vulnerable to loss justifies the
fiction. Indeed one might note that the House of Lords did
not hesitate to
uphold the doctrine in the New Zealand case of Invercargill City Council v
Hamlin stating that it was ‘nothing new’ and had been
‘feature of New Zealand law for
years’.[92] It is submitted
that the position of the minority is to be favoured and the doctrine of general
reliance is at the very least an
arguable exception to the rule relating to
nonfeasance.
(b) General Reliance and Professionals
The second objection to the proposed duty arises out of the exclusive
application of the doctrine of general reliance to cases where
reliance is
placed on public bodies for the exercise of statutory powers.
[93] As Edelman and Gray chose not to
apply the doctrine of general reliance as a unitary test they were not required
to present a justification
for this extension. The construction proposed by this
dissertation however rests entirely on the extension of the doctrine. This
can
only be achieved by referring back to the initial rationale given for the
doctrine.
In Heyman Mason J stated that general reliance was
‘the product of the grant (and exercise) of powers designed to prevent or
minimise
a risk of personal injury or disability, recognised by the legislature
as being of such magnitude or complexity that individuals
cannot, or may not,
take adequate steps for their own
protection’.[94] Under the
social contract the state is positively obliged to confer protection on
citizens. The state generally achieves this through
the actions of agents
employed to fulfil certain protective roles. The court’s softening of the
requirement of specificity
under the doctrine of general reliance is therefore
justified because the party on whom a specific statutory power is placed is
acting
as the agent of the state in ensuring the protection of members of
society. In the execution of their statutory power, such agents
effectively
stand on the other side of the social contract and, rather than being owed the
protection of their autonomy, to that
limited extent, they are under a positive
obligation to grant protection.
The proposed extension of the doctrine
is justifiable on the basis that certain parties within society, whose
professional functions
include rescue, assume the position of agents of the
state to the extent of carrying out rescue. At the core of this proposition
is
the protective nature of the role that parties such as doctors, lifeguards and
rescue services are viewed, and indeed view themselves,
as fulfilling within
society. Such roles are necessary to the peace of mind of citizens in any state,
and therefore might be distinguished
from purely professional positions such as
solicitors and businesspersons. Consequently, a citizen’s expectation that
a doctor
(B) will not stand by while he perishes is not based, as the authors
assert, on the known skills and qualifications of B so much
as it is based on
the role that B is seen to hold within society and the understanding that by
taking up that role, B has agreed
to act, within limitation, for the protection
of society. In sum, to the extent that a party’s professional role
involves rescue
they might correctly be seen to be acting as agent of the state
in carrying out the state’s protective function. Consequently,
under Mason
J’s explanation, when coupled with circumstances involving danger of
‘such magnitude or complexity that individuals
cannot, or may not, take
adequate steps for their own
protection’[95] the doctrine
of general reliance will give rise to a positive duty to rescue.
The
acceptance of this argument constitutes a clear extension of the doctrine of
general reliance as it has previously been understood.
However, as noted in
Soldano v O’Daniels, “What the courts have power to
create, they also have power to modify, reject and re-create in response to
needs of a dynamic society.
The exercise of this power ...is the strength of the
common law”.[96]
3. Application of the Duty
Accepting that the doctrine of general reliance is based upon the recognition
of a risk of ‘such magnitude or complexity that
individuals cannot, or may
not, take adequate steps for their own protection’, the duty could only
logically arise in situations
where the threat is: grave, immediate, and where
the person concerned is unable to act to protect themselves. By way of example,
the duty would not arise in the case of a patient in need of a life-saving
operation where the option to pay or contract for the
treatment is
available.[97] Such limitation is
necessary on a practical level in order to protect those subject to the duty.
Otherwise medical practitioners,
for example, would be obliged to assist any
party needing treatment regardless of the circumstances or cost, which in turn
would
create opportunities for free-riding and abuse of the medical profession.
One must also note that the existence of the duty does not mean that the
partial or total failure to carry-out a rescue constitutes
a breach of
duty.[98] Rather, liability would
depend upon all the circumstances of the case, and an application of the general
principles of breach and
the reasonable person
standard.[99] Considerations such as
the probability and gravity of risk; the expense, difficulty, and danger
involved in attempting rescue; and
any other competing interests would be taken
into account. [100] Thus, as
Edelman and Gray note, the duty may sometimes be an empty
one.[101]
Conclusion
At the heart of the common law’s rejection of a general duty to rescue
is the balance between ‘right’ and ‘autonomy’
represented in the social contract. Any limitation on individual autonomy must
be justified on the basis of legal principle rather
than notions of morality.
The greatest obstacle to a general duty is posed by the fact that any duty to
rescue necessarily contemplates
situations involving complete strangers. This is
significant as there would appear to be no arguable proximity relationship
between
the parties that could justify an exception to the rule against positive
duties. With no positive duty to rescue, there is no basis
on which a court can
find a causative link between a failure to act and the injury or death of the
victim. The duty to rescue has
therefore traditionally been viewed as merely a
moral duty lacking a principled basis sufficient to render it legally
justifiable.
However, as Edelman and Gray argue, the mistake that the
(lack of) causation/proximity type argument makes is in assuming that, for
the
purposes of rescue, all bystanders are in the same position in relation to the
person in peril. Their proposed framework for a limited version of
the duty to rescue based upon the special role that certain parties have within
society is compelling. However, I argue that their application of the assumption
of responsibility/dependence exception to the rule
against nonfeasance and their
analysis of the doctrine of general reliance are inadequate. The authors fail to
truly appreciate the
significance that the required specificity as to whom each
of these elements are directed has in relation to the creation of proximity,
and
thus to the establishment of an exception to the general rule.
If this
specificity requirement is acknowledged however, the potential for its
relaxation under the doctrine of general reliance is
of great import. I argue
that the rejection of the doctrine in Pyrenees is unfortunate and it is
the position of the minority that ought to be favoured. While the doctrine has
never been applied to private
individuals, I present a rational for the doctrine
that allows for its extension to certain individuals on the basis of the role
that they play within society. I argue that the doctrine rests upon the
law’s recognition that, in some instances, certain
bodies or individuals
act as agents for the state in the carrying out of the state’s obligation
to protect members of society
under the social contract. In such cases the
doctrine allows a softening of the requirement of specificity because it
acknowledges
that such agents effectively stand on the other side of the social
contract and, rather than being owed protection of their autonomy,
to that
limited extent, they are obliged to grant protection. Accepting this
interpretation, it is then conceivable that, where particular
professional roles
within society are viewed as fulfilling a wider function of protection, and to
the extent that the state is incapable
of otherwise effecting that protection,
such persons might also be regarded as acting as agents of the state in certain
situations.
Where this is the case, the doctrine of general reliance would
apply. I argue that this is a more apt and persuasive justification
for Edelman
and Gray’s proposed duty.
This discussion began by acknowledging
that morality alone is not capable of creating a legal duty, however, that is
not to say that
it is not a valid reason for allowing a principled extension of
the law. As Radcliffe states ‘Society has changed, and so have
its
problems and needs. The law must also change in order to address those
needs’.[102]
[1] Yuen Kun Yeu v Attorney General of Hong Kong [1987] UKPC 16; [1988] A.C. 175; [1987] 2 All E.R. 705, at 192.
[2] Osterland v Hill (1928) 160 NE 301.
[3] Allen v Hixson, (1990) 111 Ga 460, 36 SE 810
[4] Hurley v Eddingfield; (1901) 59 NE 1058l; (1901) 156 Ind. 416.
[5] Ernest J Weinrib, ‘The Case for a Duty to Rescue’ (1980) 90 Yale L.J. 247, at 266.
[6] I. Kant, (1797) The Metaphysical Elements of Justice Second Edition, (Translation by J. Ladd 1999) at 19-20, paraphrase by Weinrib, Ibid, at 266 .
[7] Steven J. Heyman, ‘Foundations of the Duty to Rescue’, (1994) 47 Vand. L. Rev 673, at 721
[8] Arthur Ripstein, ‘Three Duties to Rescue: Moral, Civil, and Criminal, (2000) 19 Law & Phil. 751, at 754.
[9] Per Lord Reid, Home Office v
Dorset Yacht Co Ltd [1970] UKHL 2; [1970] A.C. 1004; [1970] 2 All E.R, at
1026.
[10] Who, being an ethnic
‘outsider’ would have no relationship of kinship with the stranger.
[11] The Bible, Luke 10:25-36 (New Revised Standard Version, Division of the Christian Education of the national Council of Churches of Christ in the United States of America, 1989).
[12] Donoghue v Stevenson [1932] A.C. 562 (HL), at 580.
[13] Ibid 580, also see 581 where his Lordship used the term ‘proximity’.
[14] See Lord Wilberforce’s judgment in Anns v London Borough of Merton [1977] UKHL 4; [1978] AC 728; [1977] 2 All ER 492 (HL); Lord Keith’s judgment in Yuen Kun Yeu v Attorney General of Hong Kong, above n1; Lord Bridge’s judgment in Caparo Industries Plc v Dickman [1990] UKHL 2; [1990] 2 AC 605 (HL); [1990] 1 All ER 568 (HL); and Cooke P’s judgment in South Pacific Manufacturing Co Ltd v New Zealand Security Consultants Ltd [1992] 2 NZLR 282 (CA).
[15] Home Office v Dorset Yacht Co Ltd above n9, at 1060.
[16] Francis H. Bohlen , ‘The moral Duty to Aid others as a basis of Tort Liability’, (1908) 56 U. Pa. L. Rev 217, at 219.
[17] R. J Lipkin ‘Beyond Good Samaritans and Moral Monsters: An Individualistic Justification of the General Legal Duty to Rescue
(1983) 31 UCLA L. Rev. 278, at 277.
[18] John Rawls, A theory of Justice, (Harvard University Press, United States, 1971) at 407-16, paraphrase by Lipkin Ibid, at 279.
[19] Robert L Hale, ‘Prima facie Torts, Combination and Non-Feasance’ (1946) 46 Colum. L. Rev. 196, at 214.
[20] Ripstein, above n8, at 757.
[21] Ibid, at 759.
[22] Heyman, above n7, at 707.
[23] Donoghue v Stevenson, above n12, at 580.
[24] Stewart v. Pettie, [1995] 1 S.C.R. 131; also see Crocker v. Sundance Northwest Resorts Ltd., [1988] 1 S.C.R. 1186 (where an organiser of a ski competition allowed another to enter whilst intoxicated).
[25] McCallion v Dodd [1966] NZLR 710 (CA).
[26] Home Office v Dorset Yacht Co Ltd , above n9; New South Wales v Bujdoso [2005] HCA 76; (2005) 227 CLR 1; Also see discussion in C.A.L. No 14 Pty Ltd v Motor Accidents Insurance Board; C.A.L No 14 Pty Ltd v Scott [2009] HCA 47, at para 38.
[27]Jebson v Ministry of Defence [2000] 1 W.L.R. 2055; also see Barrett v Ministry of Defence [1994] EWCA Civ 7; [1995] 3 All E.R. 87.
[28] Goldman v Hargrave [1966] UKPC 2; [1967] AC 645 (PC); also see Wilson & Horton v A-G [1997] 2 NZLR 513 (CA).
[29] W Page Keeton, Dan B Dobbs, Robert E Keeton, David G Owen, Prosser and Keeton on Torts. (5th Ed, West Publishing Co., Minnesota, United States 1984) at 375.
[30] James Edelman, Nathalie Gray, ‘Developing the law of Omission: a Common Law Duty to Rescue’ (1998) 6 TLJ 240, at 241.
[31] Home Office v Dorset Yacht Co Ltd , above n9, at 1027.
[32] Clare Elaine Radcliffe, ‘A Duty to Rescue: The Good, the Bad and the Indifferent: - The Bystander’s Dilemma’ (1985) 13 Pepp. L. rev. 387, at 396.
[33] Ripstein, above n8, at 759.
[34] Caparo Industries Plc v Dickman, above n14; Rolls-Royce NZ Ltd v Carter Holt Harvey Ltd [2004] NZCA 97; [2005] 1 NZLR 324 (CA).
[35] Stovin v Wise [1996] UKHL 15; [1996] A.C. 923; [1996] 3 All E.R. 801, at 943.
[36] Home Office v Dorset Yacht Co Ltd, above n9, at 1027.
[37] Lowns v Woods (1996) Aust Torts Reports 81-376 (HCNSW). Approving the decision in Woods v Lowns ( 1995) 36 NSWLR 344.
[38] Les Habberfield, ‘Lowns v Woods and the Duty to Rescue’, (1998) 6 Tort L Rev 56, at 58.
[39] Thomas Fuance, Kumaralingam
Amerthalingam, ‘Patching up Proximity: Problems with the judicial creation
of a new medical duty
to rescue’, (1997) 5 TLJ 27, at 31.
[40] Edelman, Gray, above n31.
[41] Ibid, at 241
[42] Ibid, at 241.
[43] Hedley Byrne & Co Ltd v Heller & Partners Ltd [1963] UKHL 4; [1964] AC 465
[44] Desmond Manderson, ‘The Ethics of Proximity’, (2005) 14 GLR 295, at 315.
[45] Ibid, at 315.
[46] The Council of the Shire of Suntherland v Heyman (1985) Aust Torts Reports 80-322, at 68,324; [1985] HCA 41; (1985) 157 CLR 424.
[47] White and another v Jones and others [1995] UKHL 5; [1995] 2 AC 207.
[48] Radcliffe, above n33, at 396.
[49] Per Bedlam L.J Barrett v Ministry of Defence, above n27, at 1224, emphasis added.
[50] The Council of the Shire of Suntherland v Heyman, above n47, at 463-464, emphasis added.
[51] Ibid, at 463-464
[52] Parramatta City Council v Lutz [1985] HCA 41; (1985) 157 CLR 424 ; (1985) 60 ALR 1.
[53] Edelman, Gray, above n31, at 243.
[54] Casley-Smith v FS Evans & Sons Pty Ltd (No 5) (1988) 67 LGRA 108; Nagle v Rottnest Island Authority (1989) Aust Torts Rep 80-298; Hicks v Lake Macquarie City Council (No 2) (1992) 77 LGRA 269; Romeo v Conservation Commission of the Northern Territory [1994] NTSC 106; (1994) 123 FLR 71; Alec Finlayson Pty Ltd v Armidale City Council [1994] FCA 1198; (1994) 51 FCR 378 ; 123 ALR 155; Northern Territory of Australia v Deutscher Klub (Darwin) Inc (1994) 122 FLR 135.
[55] Invercargill City Council v Hamlin [1996] UKPC 56; [1996] AC 624; [1996] 1 NZLR 513, at 519 See Hope v. Manukau City Council (unreported), 2 August 1976; Brown v Heathcote County Council [1986] NZCA 451; [1986] 1 NZLR 76, at 81; Also see statements made by Cooke P in South Pacific Manufacturing Co Ltd v New Zealand Security Consultants & Investigations Ltd, above n14, at 297.
[56] Pyrenees Shire Council v Day [1998] HCA 3; 192 CLR 330 [1998] Aust Torts Reports 64,673 (81-456).
[57] Edelman, Gray, above n31, at 243.
[58] Hedley Byrne & Co Ltd v Heller & Partners, above n44, at 529.
[59] Edelman, Gray, above n31, at 246.
[60] Subject to policy considerations, for example it is clear that there are limitations on the laws willingness to impose liability on public bodies where such would adversely affect the allocation or use of resources. See Hill v West Yorkshire Police [1989] AC 53 (HL); Smith v Chief Constable of Sussex [2008] 3 WLR 593 (HL).
[61] Edelman, Gray, above n31, at 241.
[62] See above Section 2.1.
[63] Hawkins v Clayton (1988) 164 CLR 539.
[64] Edelman, Gray, above n31, at 244.
[65] Hawkins v Clayton , above n64, 578-9.
[66] Ibid, at 596.
[67] Edelman, Gray, above n31, at 242.
[68] Ibid, at 244
[69] Ibid, at 243.
[70] See above section 1.3 and n26.
[71] Edelman, Gray, above n32, at 244.
[72] Pyrenees Shire Council v
Day above n56.
[73]
Pyrenees Shire Council v Day above n56.
[74] Ibid, at para 163.
[75] Ibid, at para19.
[76] Ibid, at para 203.
[77] Stovin v Wise , above n36, at 464.
[78] Mary-Anne Simpson, ‘What Amounts to an Assumption of Responsibility’ [1995] 1 NZLJ 61, at 62.
[79] Sutradhar v Natural Environment Research Council [2006] EWHC 3083; [2006] 4 All ER 490 (HL).
[80] Caparo Industries Plc v Dickman above n14, at 609 citing Cardozo CJ in Ultramares Corporation v. Touche (1931) 174 N.E. 441, at 444.
[81] Stephen Todd, The Law of Torts in New Zealand, (4th ed. Brookers, New Zealand, 2005), at 155-6. Emphasis added.
[82] Caparo Industries Plc v Dickman, above n14, at 622.
[83] Hawkins v Clayton , above n64, See above section 2.2.1.2.
[84] Ibid, Per Deane J at 579 and Per Gaudron J at 597.
[85] Per Gaudron J, Hawkins v Clayton, above n64, at 597.
[86] Radcliffe, above n33, at 396.
[87] Other cases demonstrating this approach are: White and another v Jones and others, above n48; Hill v Van Erp (1986) 162 CLR 341; Gartside v Sheffield Young & Ellis [1983] NZCA 37; [1983] NZLR 37 (CA).
[88] See Brownie Wills v Shrimpton [1998] 2 NZLR 320 (CA); Kapfunde v Abbey National plc [1999] ICR 1 (CA).
[89] Pyrenees Shire Council v Day, above n56, at para 62.
[90] See Tipping J in A-G v Carter [2003] NZCA 48; [2003] 2 NZLR 160 (CA), at 168.
[91] Pyrenees Shire Council v Day, above n56, at para 107-9.
[92] Invercargill City Council v Hamlin, above n 56, at 519.
[93] Indeed the cases almost exclusively concern the powers of local councils or council regulatory bodies - See Invercargill City Council v Hamlin Ibid; Hope v. Manukau City Council, above n56; Brown v Heathcote County Council above n56.
[94] The Council of the Shire of Suntherland v Heyman, above n47, at 463-4.
[95] Ibid, at 463-4.
[96] Soldano v O’Daniels (1983) 141 Cal.App.3d 443, 190 Cal.Rptr. 310.
[97] See Weinrib, above n5, at 275.
[98] See McHugh J’s discussion of the scope of the duty arising out of cases of general reliance in Pyrenees Shire Council v Day, above n57, at para 109.
[99] Lipkin, above n17, at 274.
[100] Wyong Shire Council v Shirt [1980] HCA 12; (1980) 146 CLR 40, at 47-8
[101] Edelman, Gray, above n31, at 248.
[102] Radcliffe, above n33, at 388.
NZLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/NZLawStuJl/2011/1.html