NZLII Home | Databases | WorldLII | Search | Feedback

Public Interest Law Journal of New Zealand

You are here:  NZLII >> Databases >> Public Interest Law Journal of New Zealand >> 2018 >> [2018] NZPubIntLawJl 9

Database Search | Name Search | Recent Articles | Noteup | LawCite | Download | Help

Norton, Louis --- "Is 'defensive practice' defensible? Chilling effects and responsible administration with regard to public authority negligence claims in New Zealand" [2018] NZPubIntLawJl 9; (2018) 5 PILJNZ 5


(2018) Is “Defensive Practice” Defensible? 5

51

Public Interest Law Journal of New Zealand

(2018) 5 PILJNZ 5

ARTICLE

Is Defensive PracticeDefensible? Chilling Effects and Responsible Administration with Regard to Public Authority Negligence Claims in New Zealand

LOUIS NORTON*

Negligence liability for public authorities is often hamstrung by public policy concerns negating a duty of care. A major policy concern is that monetary liability will have a “chilling effect”. Public officials are sometimes presumed to become detrimentally defensive in performing their duties for fear of incurring liability. An opposing school of thought holds that monetary liability would have the positive effect of enforcing prudence, higher standards of care and responsible administration. While the issue has been litigated extensively in comparable jurisdictions, the overall nature and scope of this “defensive practice” concern in New Zealand is less well defined. In this article, I begin by conducting a survey of New Zealand case law relying on, or dismissing, the concern and attempt to establish its current position. In the latter section, I consider what the role of the defensive practice concern should be in New Zealand. Identifying the key universal factors bearing upon the liability equation with examination of both case law and legal commentary, I attempt to set out a reasoned calculus for assessing negligence liability in a given public authority context.

* The paper on which this article was based won second prize in the 2018 LEANZ (Law and Economics Association of New Zealand) essay competition. The author wishes to thank Associate Professor Hanna Wilberg of the University of Auckland for her assistance and supervision in preparing this paper. The paper was completed in partial fulfilment of the coursework requirements for LAWHONS 742.

I Introduction

Finding that a public authority owes a duty of care in negligence exposes it to monetary liability. Consequently, public operators will become defensive in carrying on public services. This is what the landmark decision in Hill v Chief Constable of West Yorkshire leads us to believe.1 In that case, the House of Lords held that imposing liability “may lead to the exercise of a function being carried on in a detrimentally defensive frame of mind”.2 The Court declined to find that a duty of care was owed by the police. For many years, the Hill principle conferred a blanket immunity on police in the United Kingdom against actions in negligence. While this trend was qualified very recently in the United Kingdom Supreme Court,3 the influence of the Hill decision can be discerned across a wide range of public authority contexts. “Defensive practice” has often been applied as a pretext for dispensing with public authority liability generally.4 Courts have left the door open to impose liability where policy considerations in favour of a duty are sufficiently strong. 5 One such consideration is that deterrence of wrongful conduct, not defensiveness, will result from liability. This possibility was countenanced in Lord Keith’s judgment in Hill.6 An uncertain dichotomy emerges in relation to the behavioural effect of monetary liability—with the undesirable consequences of defensive practice weighing against a finding for duty, and the positive effect of deterrence weighing in favour.

Little uniformity emerges from the relevant authorities. Within the two-stage duty of

care inquiry,7 defensive practice concerns have often seemed to be applied arbitrarily. Much of the leading case law on defensive practice concerns and deterrence was decided in the United Kingdom. New Zealand authority is comparatively limited. This article accordingly explores both what the position on defensive practice in New Zealand currently is, and what it should be. In the first section, I canvass New Zealand case law that has either invoked the concern or dismissed it. In the latter, I examine the dichotomy between defensiveness and deterrence and attempt to set out a reasoned framework of important considerations to which the courts should have regard. The breadth of factors bearing upon the defensive practice concern is potentially limitless. The purpose of this article is to bring into focus the relevant considerations and their relative importance, yielding a calculus for assessing the applicability of the defensive practice concern. This principled application would abrogate the seemingly random, ad hoc nature of the current approach, while retaining the flexibility to deal with cases on their individual merits.

II Survey of New Zealand Case Law

The New Zealand position must be determined. I here outline a representative range of statements on the chilling effects of raising defensive practice concerns, and responsible

1 Hill v Chief Constable of West Yorkshire [1989] 1 AC 53 (HL).

2 At 63. For a fuller exposition on the implications of defensive practice, see Lord Keith’s judgment in this case generally.

3 Robinson v Chief Constable of West Yorkshire Police [2018] UKSC 4, [2018] AC 736.

4 Elguzouli-Daf v Commissioner of Police of the Metropolis [1994] EWCA Civ 4; [1995] QB 335 (CA); Mitchell v Glasgow City Council [2009] UKHL 11, [2009] 1 AC 874; and Home Office v Dorset Yacht Co Ltd [1970] UKHL 2; [1970] AC 1004 (HL) at 1033 per Lord Reid.

5 Swinney v Chief Constable of Northumbria Police Force [1996] EWCA Civ 1322; [1997] QB 464 (CA).

6 Hill, above n 1, at 63.

7 South Pacific Manufacturing Co Ltd v New Zealand Security Consultants & Investigations Ltd

[1992] 2 NZLR 282 (CA) at 294–295 and 305–306.

administration, highlighting the positive deterrent effect of liability. I summarise the most relevant lines of reasoning emerging from the body of case law. This initial process of contextualisation highlights the volatile, and sometimes arbitrary New Zealand jurisprudential approaches to liability calculations.

A Property transactions

Gregory v Rangitikei District Council concerned the Rangitikei District Council conducting a sale of property by tender.8 It declined to sell to Gregory, the highest tenderer, and negotiated with a different purchaser. In failing to advertise the proposal to sell the property privately, the council did not follow statutory procedures and therefore breached its duty of care to Gregory.9 Loss was reasonably foreseeable. Defensive practice was of little concern. The duty required nothing more than compliance with statute.10 McGechan J determined that the duty would improve standards of practice, and that insurance would blunt the economic burden of liability such that no detrimental influence would bear upon the authority’s behaviour.11

Gregory is relevant in examining judicial attitudes toward the defensive

practice/deterrence equation. It suggests that where loss-spreading measures are available, these provide a compelling reason to impose liability pursuant to the goal of responsible administration of public authorities. Gregory is also authority for the proposition that a common law duty might be warranted in the interest of deterrence if it runs tandem to a statutory duty.

B Medical practitioners

The plaintiff in S v Midcentral District Health Board (No 2) alleged negligence after she, a mental health patient, was raped by another patient in the defendant’s care.12 William Young J held that inducement of defensive medicine was not decisive in disposing of liability.13 Internal processes and disciplinary proceedings would be more likely to induce defensive medicine than the possibility that clinicians’ employers face a claim for exemplary damages.14 The close proximity relationship justified a duty.15

This case highlights two important lines of reasoning in New Zealand jurisprudence relating to the defensiveness/deterrence calculation. First, it illustrates that judicial concerns about defensive practice are less acute when there is a strong relationship of proximity between the tortfeasor and the injured party. Secondly, the judgment contemplates the effect of liability relative to internal organisational pressures. This contributes to New Zealand commentary on the viability of accountability measures outside of negligence accountability.

In Ellis v Counties Manukau District Health Board, the question was whether the District

Health Board (DHB) owed a duty to a medically insane plaintiff to detain and prevent him

8 Gregory v Rangitikei District Council [1994] NZHC 1448; [1995] 2 NZLR 208 (HC). 9 At 227.

10 At 230.

11 At 230.

12 S v Midcentral District Health Board (No 2) [2004] NZAR 342 (HC).

13 At [47]. Defensive medicine here may influence, for example, the decision of whether to grant a “leave of absence” in respect of a patient who is subject to an inpatient order.

14 At [47].

15 At [48].

from causing harm.16 The plaintiff murdered his father after being released from DHB custody. Potter J stated that health professionals could become unduly defensive if “continually faced with the spectre of exposure to common law claims in negligence”.17 The statutory scheme empowered health professionals with a broad discretion, and provided that detention be a last resort.18 It was considered inappropriate to impose a duty of care to detain. Potter J couched part of her reasoning in the fact that other remedies were available to the plaintiff, such as lodging a complaint with the Health and Disability Commissioner, or a civil claim before the Human Rights Review Tribunal.19

Ellis underscores the close correlation between broad discretionary powers and

defensive practice concerns. Moreover, Potter J’s discussion of alternative remedies suggests that where an injured party’s claim might be vindicated through recourse to other measures than liability, this will also weigh against the deterrence argument.

C Police

The High Court in Evers v Attorney-General declined to find that a duty was owed where police were alleged to have negligently failed to stop the illegal activities of youths at a beach resort.20 Chambers J reviewed the English line of authority on police negligence and defensive practice.21 Liability would not engender higher standards of care, but rather a diversion of resources from crime suppression.22 Failures to control a third party should only exceptionally attract a duty.23 The Court struck out the negligence claim.

An important feature to note is the Court’s willingness to impute to the police a privileged stature. There is substantial public interest in the robust administration of the police’s public duties, and risks attendant on excessive fettering. Evers signals that police, and perhaps other authorities providing high-utility public services, will more readily attract protection from liability. This case also provides a counterpoint to the ‘close proximity’ argument outlined above in S v Midcentral.24 Evers involved an alleged failure by police to control the actions of an unrelated third party. While S v Midcentral also involved a failure to control a third party, the defendant authority in that case had an established control relationship with both victim and perpetrator. Extent of control, then, is relevant in considering the weight of defensive practice concerns and the appropriateness of a duty generally.

Fyfe v Attorney General concerned an allegedly negligent arrest.25 McGechan J noted that it was uncontroversial that police do not owe a duty in matters of general policing and exercise of their discretion.26 However, he stated that “[p]olice can be liable in negligence in respect of the exercise of law enforcement functions ... liability depends upon circumstances”.27 This is a departure from Hill and Evers. Police negligence claims should

16 Ellis v Counties Manukau District Health Board [2006] NZHC 826; [2007] 1 NZLR 196 (HC). 17 At [171].

18 At [175].

19 At [171].

20 Evers v Attorney-General [2000] NZAR 372 (HC).

21 Chambers J specifically applied Hill, above n 1; Alexandrou v Oxford [1993] 4 All ER 328 (CA); and Osman v Ferguson [1992] EWCA Civ 8; [1993] 4 All ER 344 (CA).

22 At [30].

23 At [33].

24 S v Midcentral, above n 12.

25 Fyfe v Attorney-General [2001] NZAR 498 (HC). 26 At [58].

27 At [62].

not be arbitrarily struck out on public policy grounds.28 Instead, given the range of possible circumstances involving egregious police conduct, public policy demanded “robust judicial control”.29

Fyfe suggests that despite the deference shown to the reasoning of the House of Lords in earlier cases,30 defensive practice concerns will not, in New Zealand, shield police from liability in all circumstances. Evers and Fyfe indicate that the New Zealand approach to assessing liability, both in terms of induced defensiveness and positive deterrence, turns less on the question of public authority privilege than it does other persuasive factors in the duty inquiry—like proximity. It is relevant that unlike Hill and Evers, this case did not concern a police failure to control a third party.

D Building and land consents

In Morrison v Upper Hutt City Council, an authority granted, and then revoked, a building consent because the development fell outside the requirements of the district scheme.31 The plaintiff was granted a specified departure, but costs were higher than they would have been if the application had been granted in the first instance. There was sufficient proximity. The Court stressed that the statutory scheme gave the authority broad discretion.32 Ratepayers occasionally had to be detrimentally affected by the authority’s decisions for the scheme to be administered efficiently. 33 The question was barely justiciable and a negligence standard was inappropriate.34 Appeal to the Planning Tribunal was considered the appropriate recourse.35 The Court dispensed of liability.

Bella Vista Resort Ltd v Western Bay of Plenty District Council involved an authority

issuing consents for the construction of a lodge and conference facility.36 It was assumed that neighbours had consented. However, the neighbours successfully took proceedings for judicial review. The developer alleged that the council had breached its duty of care to ensure that the consent applications were correctly processed. No duty was found.

Robertson J held that the council was entitled to rely on advice that consent had been obtained. 37 Otherwise, the authority would be required to go behind the information placed before it, creating administrative delays.38 It was important that the applicants had alternative forms of redress available.39

Chambers J considered that proximity requirements had been met.40 However there were justiciability issues, as the plaintiffs had asked the council to deal with their application on a non-notified basis, and they now wanted to sue the council for “having adopted the very submissions they urged on it”.41

28 At [61].

29 At [61].

30 Evers, above n 20.

31 Morrison v Upper Hutt City Council [1998] NZCA 271; [1998] 2 NZLR 331 (CA). 32 At 338.

33 At 338.

34 At 338.

35 At 338.

36 Bella Vista Resort Ltd v Western Bay of Plenty District Council [2007] NZCA 33, [2007] 3 NZLR 429.

37 At [56] per Robertson J.

38 At [56] and [57].

39 At [60].

40 At [88] per Chambers J.

41 At [90].

William Young P cited the danger in dealing with public policy factors on the basis of assumptions.42 He ultimately held that, as in Morrison, a regulatory body carrying out a quasi-judicial function should not owe a duty.43

In Monticello Holdings Ltd v Selwyn District Council, Gendall J found that a local authority was under no duty to inform a land developer that the land it had purchased was contaminated.44 A duty would fetter the authority’s ability to issue resource consents in its quasi-judicial capacity.45 He commented on the tendency for plaintiffs to seek relief from local authorities because of their perceived financial means.46

These cases highlight several factors bearing upon the defensiveness/deterrence calculation. As in Ellis, statutory powers of discretion in these cases tended to bolster defensive practice concerns. The availability of alternative modes of redress is relevant. The cases also demonstrate that the nature of a given authority, and the extent of its powers of adjudication, are relevant to determining the strength of defensive practice and deterrence concerns. Bella Vista and Monticello particularly emphasise that quasi-judicial decision makers are typically not the subject of duties, and that in this context defensive practice concerns hold more water.

E Leaky buildings

In Attorney-General v Body Corporate 200200 (Sacramento) a body corporate sought damages in relation to leaky buildings from the Attorney-General, as statutory successor of the Building Industry Authority (BIA). 47 Proximity between the BIA and the building owners was limited.48 William Young J considered quasi-judicial authorities could not owe duties of care. Liability would induce the kind of “over-vigilance” that the applicable statutory scheme was designed to avoid.49 It would create an environment in which it would be “impracticable for building certifiers to operate”.50

In Attorney-General v North Shore City Council (The Grange),51 Arnold J considered that

the BIA performed a quasi-judicial role and the imposition of a duty would impede the flow of information to the responsible Minister. Overriding policy concerns included whether the duty would be consistent with the prescriptions of governing legislation, that quasi- legislative functions are not properly the subject of duties, that policy-oriented powers are less likely to attract duties than operational ones, and the limited extent of control exercised by the authority over the loss-causing activity.52

In relation to the wider defensive practice/deterrence calculus, these authorities reaffirm the relevance of proximity, extent of control, and the particular nature of the defendant authority as discussed in the cases canvassed above.53

42 At [71] per William Young P. 43 At [75].

44 Monticello Holdings Ltd v Selwyn District Council [2015] NZHC 1674, [2016] 2 NZLR 148. 45 At [88].

46 At [62].

47 Attorney-General v Body Corporate 200200 [2007] 1 NZLR 95 (CA) [Sacramento]. 48 At [61].

49 At [93], with regard to the Building Act 1991. 50 At [62].

51 Attorney-General v North Shore City Council [2010] NZCA 324, [2011] 1 NZLR 178 [The Grange]. 52 At [32].

53 As concerns proximity, see for example S v Midcentral, above n 12; and compare Evers, above n 20. As concerns the extent of control, see Evers, above n 20. As concerns the nature of the authority, see generally Bella Vista, above n 36 and Monticello, above n 44.

F Child protection

Attorney-General v Prince and Gardner involved an alleged failure to protect a child by omitting to investigate a complaint made under the Children and Young Persons Act 1974.54 Proximity was established.55 Richardson P, for the majority, considered a common law duty to investigate would enhance the obligations placed on the department in the relevant legislation.56 Henry J dissented, holding that no duty was owed on the grounds that “potential tortfeasors may act defensively, to the possible ultimate detriment of the young person”. 57 He emphasised the discretion exercised by social workers and the problematic width of the duty.58

Prince demonstrates a tension that is not easily resolved. Strong rationales underlying

a push for positive deterrence (such as pre-existing statutory duties59 and close proximity relationships 60 ), and those tending to add weight to defensive practice concerns (the unimpeded exercise of discretionary powers)61 are both represented. That the court was divided reinforces the apparent uncertainty in the defensiveness/deterrence balancing act, and the weight afforded to these factors in judicial contemplation of public authority liability.

In B v Attorney General the Privy Council considered whether a duty was owed to a

father suspected (later cleared) of sexually abusing his daughters.62 Further, it had to be determined whether a duty was owed to the children for trauma from being removed from their father’s custody.63 Lord Nicholls held that, in accordance with Prince,64 a common law duty to the children should be recognised.65 No duty was owed to the father. Given that the interests of an alleged perpetrator and a victim are incompatible, it would be impermissible to find a duty owed to the former at the same time as one owed to the latter.66 The interest of the child must prevail. This case therefore raised a strong conflict of duties formulation of defensive practice.

Conflict of duties is elaborated on at length in the latter section of this article. For immediate purposes, it is helpful to think of conflicting duties as a counter-point to the pre-existing duty argument raised in Gregory and Prince. The pre-existing duty argument involves a common law duty reinforcing an existing, complementary duty imposed by statute in the interest of more responsible administration. Conversely, the conflict of duties situation weighs strongly against the imposition of a common law duty. Where a proposed duty would conflict with the existing public duty of a given authority, this will necessarily impede that authority’s agency—de facto defensive practice resulting.

54 Attorney-General v Prince and Gardner [1998] 1 NZLR 262 (CA). 55 At 282.

56 At 284.

57 At 289.

58 At 289.

59 Weighing in favour of deterrence in cases such as Gregory, above n 8.

60 Weighing in favour of deterrence in cases such as S v Midcentral, above n 12.

61 As stressed in Ellis, above n 16, and Morrison, above n 31.

62 B v Attorney-General [2003] UKPC 61, [2004] 3 NZLR 145. 63 At [1].

64 Prince, above n 54.

65 B v Attorney-General, above n 62, at [27]. 66 At [30].

G Parolee supervision

Hobson v Attorney-General raised the question of whether the Department of Corrections was liable in negligence for failing to supervise parolee William Bell, who had carried out a robbery and triple homicide at a Returned and Services Association.67 William Young P held that liability would induce a higher likelihood of offending. Over-cautiousness on the part of probation officers would impede the rehabilitation of parolees.68 The proposed duty would conflict with the statutory purposes of the parole scheme to reintegrate offenders.69 The accident compensation scheme excluded the injured party, Ms Couch, from seeking compensatory damages. 70 Appropriate redress was not a counterweight to policy considerations that might be compromised by a duty of care.

Chambers J considered risk minimisation efforts could cripple efficiency across a range of responsibilities involving detention, supervision and monitoring. 71 He expressed scepticism that a duty would promote higher standards of administration. 72 He cited proximity and floodgates concerns, and the discretion exercised by the authority as pointing against liability.73 The lack of direct control exercised by the department over the offender was important.74

Hammond J, dissenting, questioned whether the “tort dress had been overshrunk” in New Zealand. Ms Couch primarily sought public accountability and Hammond J considered that this could only be appropriately vindicated by imposition of a duty.75 He held that the negligence claim should not be struck out and, referring to the work of Basil S Markesinis and others, 76 urged that judges not be too quick to invoke defensive practice at the expense of tort law’s wider objectives of deterrence.77

The majority judgments in Hobson emphasise several relevant considerations

identified in the above cases. They also show how these factors bear upon the defensive practice question. William Young P and Chambers J canvass proximity and extent of control issues, the importance of the authority’s discretion, and the existence of a possible conflict between the proposed duty in negligence and the statutory framework underlying the parole scheme. They are persuasive in arguing that given New Zealand’s accident compensation scheme, matters of appropriate compensation should not weigh heavily against defensive practice concerns where the claim concerns personal injury. Hobson suggests that the presence of some or all of these factors should overwhelm the type of accountability/deterrence argument put forth by Hammond J.

The Supreme Court was more equivocal. Hobson came before the Court on appeal.78 Elias CJ held that dispensing of liability on the basis of presupposition was erroneous.79 She was also critical of the determination that a common law duty would be inconsistent

67 Hobson v Attorney-General [2006] NZCA 409; [2007] 1 NZLR 374 (CA). 68 At [122].

69 At [122] and [125].

70 At [127].

71 At [176] per Chambers J. 72 At [182].

73 At [170] and [175].

74 At [180] and [187].

75 At [75].

76 See Basil S Markesinis and others Tortious Liability of Statutory Bodies: A Comparative and Economic Analysis of Five English Cases (Hart Publishing, Oregon, 1999) at 109.

77 Hobson, above n 67, at [77].

78 Couch v Attorney-General [2008] NZSC 45, [2008] 3 NZLR 725. 79 At [36].

with the statutory framework—this approach would immunise the Probation Service from actions in negligence, no matter how great the want of care.80 A common law duty would instead “march hand in hand” with its statutory responsibilities.81 Elias CJ considered it premature to strike out the claim. It was possible that there was a sufficient proximate relationship to found a duty given the high amount of control the Probation Service exercised over Bell.82

Tipping J, for the majority, agreed that it was arguable that a duty was owed. However, in his estimation the case, as pleaded, did not disclose sufficient proximity.83 Tipping J touched on the policy arm of the duty inquiry only lightly. He declined to make any determinations as to the import of any factors existing on both sides of the policy equation.84

These two decisions highlight judicial divergence on the question of pre-existing duties in the public authority context. William Young P’s judgment in Hobson held that a common law duty would conflict with the existing parole scheme—a conflicting duties formulation of defensive practice.85 Elias CJ in Couch v Attorney-General asserted in the alternative that the duty contended for would complement the Probation Service’s existing charges. That fact that these two judges came to different conclusions as to the claim’s viability demonstrates that any proposed duty should be scrutinised: assessing whether its effect in practice would be to reinforce prescribed obligations, or, alternatively, to fetter a contrasting set of obligations.

H Ministerial error

Takaro Properties Ltd v Rowling concerned the Minister of Finance’s alleged negligence in refusing to grant consent for a scheme that would raise Takaro’s capital.86 Takaro then went into receivership. Lord Keith reiterated that it was hoped that liability would induce higher standards of care, but that in some situations harmful consequences would arise that is, chilling effects).87 As the Minister’s decision was capable of being described as having a policy rather than operational character, the alleged negligence skirted suitability for judicial resolution.88 The Court considered that errors of law by a Minister or public authority could only rarely be described as negligent, and that a Minister would not usually be under a duty to seek legal advice.89 Considered wholly, it was dubious that liability in negligence was appropriate.90

Takaro is relevant in illustrating the correlation between justiciability issues and defensive practice concerns. Much as in Morrison, Bella Vista and The Grange,91 Takaro

affirms that where the exercise of powers is policy-oriented rather than operational, or where negligence liability may otherwise be an inappropriate measure, judicial fears of defensive practice will tend to be more acute.

80 At [36].

81 At [58].

82 At [72].

83 At [112].

84 At [128].

85 Hobson, above n 67, at [122].

86 Takaro Properties Ltd v Rowling [1987] 2 NZLR 700 (PC). 87 At 710.

88 At 709.

89 At 709.

90 At 711.

91 Morrison, above n 31 at 338; Bella Vista, above n 36 at [90]; and The Grange, above 51 at [32].

I Summary

The authorities disclose little consistency on the position on defensive practice in New Zealand. The policy concern has been applied or dispensed with on a case by case basis— often seemingly at whim. Particular judges are also internally inconsistent, without much indication of which factors decisively weighed for or against the concern in different contexts. 92 There is little to guide us in determining whether defensive practice is an appropriate consideration in a particular situation, and to what extent it should insulate public authorities from liability.

The most concrete observation is that defensive practice/deterrence concerns are often parasitic on the strength of other factors in the duty inquiry. Where there is a strong proximity relationship or other policy factors pointing toward a duty, the deterrent effect of liability is often stressed.93 Equally, where proximity is weak, or other policy concerns militate against the duty, this has tended to strengthen defensive practice considerations. 94 The overriding impression is that defensive practice/deterrence arguments are accessory concerns that are not usually determinative of liability per se. Possible exceptions are cases involving a strong conflict of duties, or where the discretion of the authority is not to be interfered with.95

If it is true that defensive practice is a secondary or even tertiary consideration, this would go some way in explaining the inconsistent state of New Zealand jurisprudence. Peripheral to commonly cited policy factors like floodgates arguments, proximity, and justiciability issues, defensive practice has proved to be the perpetual bridesmaid in the greater liability equation. Uncertainty, to some extent, is part and parcel of tort law. The scattershot nature of the approach to defensive practice in New Zealand, however, must be considered unsatisfactory. The irresistible conclusion to be drawn from the New Zealand authorities is that there is scope to proceed on a more reasoned basis than has so far been apparent.

III The Defensiveness/Deterrence Dichotomy

I here consider what the New Zealand position should be by outlining the most important factors to which the court should have regard in assessing liability. This exposition allows us to both critique and explain much of the existing body of New Zealand case law. It also shines a light on important considerations that New Zealand courts have not tended to expressly countenance.

A The empirical dimension

A common reservation about the validity of the defensive practice concern is the apparent lack of empirical evidence supporting it.96 Fears of over-cautiousness on the part of the public authority often arise from supposition. The countervailing argument—that

92 See, for example, William Young J’s vacillations on defensive practice between S v Midcentral, above n 12; Bella Vista, above n 36; Sacramento, above n 47; and Hobson, above n 67.

93 See, for example, S v Midcentral, above n 12; and Prince, above n 54.

94 See, for example, Evers, above n 20; and Hobson, above n 67.

95 B v Attorney-General, above n 62; and Ellis, above n 16.

96 See, for example, Claire McIvor “Getting Defensive about Police Negligence: The Hill Principle, the Human Rights Act 1998 and the House of Lords” (2010) 69 CLJ 133 at 135.

improved performance and responsible administration will be the outcome of liability— must be subject to the same uncertainty.97

The Law Commission of England and Wales has examined the available evidence on the empirical issue.98 It concluded that defensiveness in response to liability was a fear more imagined than real. 99 Public bodies consider liability in decision making, but in practice do not significantly alter behaviour. 100 The Commission recognised that deterrence of negligent behaviour could result in improved public services.101 However, it considered that any general inference of the behavioural influence of liability was difficult to draw.102 The Commission qualified these conclusions by conceding that any observable change in public authority behaviour would likely reflect defensive practice rather than effective administration.103

Jef De Mot and Michael Faure adopt an economic framework to analyse chilling effects.104 They argue that such effects will occur when a potential injurer takes risk-averse measures beyond the socially and economically optimal level. 105 Socially desirable activities may cease where the benefit accruing to the injurer is overwhelmed by the costs of precaution and liability. In the case of a public authority, this fear is much more acute. Unlike private tortfeasors, who would pay all the costs associated with precaution themselves, public authorities usually balance the (externalised) costs of inaction and intervention. 106 The authority accordingly becomes inclined to go to the extreme in preventing risks, as it does not bear the precaution cost itself.

The Law Commission characterises this situation as related to the question of appropriate incentives. Effective administration should result from incentivising authorities to the degree that they invest sufficiently in harm reduction. Defensive administration would result from over investment to this end.107 A related difficulty is that it is normally a high threshold to establish breach on the part of a public authority. This means that the typical authority would not tend to feel obligated to invest heavily in harm prevention where it can instead protect itself through compliance to a reasonable standard of care.108

The defensive practice concern in New Zealand is amorphous. This exacerbates the possibility for chilling effects to occur. Where the standards to which a public authority must comply are established and definitive, the authority only needs to ensure that its behaviour meets that standard. Where the law is ambiguous, chilling behaviour is more likely.109 A lack of information about the limits of liability or the standard expected makes ascertaining the appropriate level of investment in harm-reduction difficult—leading

97 Michael v Chief Constable of South Wales Police [2015] UKSC 2, [2015] AC 1732 at [121]–[122].

98 Law Commission Administrative Redress: Public Bodies and the Citizen (Law Commission, Consultation Paper No 187, June 2008).

99 At [6.18].

100 At [6.39].

101 At [B.81].

102 At [B.83].

103 At [B.83].

104 Jef De Mot and Michael Faure “Public authority liability and the chilling effect” (2014) 22 Tort L Rev 120.

105 At 122.

106 At 124.

107 Law Commission, above n 98, at [B.23]. 108 At [B.24].

109 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 125.

authorities to maximise investment to the extent that “de facto defensive administration is the result”.110

Uncertain legal standards and externalisation of costs related to risk-aversion therefore create an environment in which strong chilling effects may come to bear.111 As public bodies are not subject to competitive market forces, any induced defensiveness affecting the quality of service provision would not be challenged by individuals transferring their custom elsewhere. Public authorities, then, lack compelling disincentives to invest heavily in risk-aversion measures.112 De Mot and Faure conclude that “chilling effects are not a complete illusion”.113

Norman G Poythress and Stanley L Brodsky conducted a study on the deterrent function of tort in the context of mental health practitioners.114 They concluded that fear of litigation reduces quality of care generally, increases risk of institutionalisation and reduces staff-to-patient ratios.115 The pathogenic effect of litigation-induced fear led to indiscriminate practices by clinical staff such as refusing to discharge patients where discharge was reasonable and warranted.116 The authors stress that different contexts will produce different cost-benefit profiles, and as such these findings might not be universally applicable. 117 From these studies, however, it appears that bare assumptions that defensive practice is merely illusory are not well-founded.

Empirical evidence receives limited acknowledgment in New Zealand case law. Most judgments avoid referencing such evidence entirely, and baldly assert that either defensiveness or deterrence is likely to result from liability. Greater attention to the considerations detailed above is one way the courts can introduce greater coherence to the law as it relates to behavioural influence on public authorities. For example, if we re-evaluate Hobson 118 in light of the Poythress and Brodsky study, the arguments of William Young P and Chambers J hold more water than was later credited by the Supreme Court. One of Elias CJ’s main bones of contention in Couch was that the defensive practice argument was predicated on hypothetical facts.119 Parolee supervision can be viewed as a similar context to mental health practitioners, who also exercise a similar supervisory function in the public interest. We may reason by analogy that similar quality-of-care impacts and service dilution to that described in the study would have materialised had liability eventually been imposed in the Hobson and Couch litigation. The Supreme Court’s determination that policy considerations disclosed no justification for summary dismissal, then, may have been at least partially faulty. Attentiveness to the body of empirical evidence should mitigate the possibility of flawed decisions being arrived at on the basis of supposition.

110 Law Commission, above n 98, at [B.27].

111 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 124.

112 Law Commission, above n 98, at [B.25].

113 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 133.

114 Norman G Poythress and Stanley L Brodsky “In the Wake of a Negligent Release Law Suit: An Investigation of Professional Consequences and Institutional Impact on a State Psychiatric Hospital” (1992) 16 Law and Human Behavior 155.

115 At 159.

116 At 172.

117 At 173.

118 Hobson, above n 67.

119 Couch, above n 78, at [36].

B Quantum of damages

Substantial damages attract defensive behaviour. Plaintiffs have less incentive to pursue small claims. Larger claims induce higher risk aversion measures, and small claims are not likely to strain the budgets of large public departments. 120 Low payouts attract little publicity, so the adverse reputational effects of claims entering the public domain are diminished.121 While it is reasonable to assume that this holds true for positive effects of deterrence, De Mot and Faure argue that liability’s sanction is comparatively weak.122 They note that only a fraction of victims recover damages from the tort system, and that due to internal budgetary reasons, liability costs are not always proportionately charged to the responsible department.123

Quantum of damages is not expressly related to the question of deterrence and defensiveness in the New Zealand case law. Greater clarity might be achieved by the courts explicitly contemplating what amount of damages would produce the best set of incentives and sanctions on public authorities. It is important consider whether, as De Mot and Faure argue, substantial payouts might be against the greater public interest in tending to engender defensive behaviour more so than deterrence of wrongful conduct.

C Insurance

Frequently, damages awards are paid by the defendant authority’s insurance company. This blunts the deterrent effect of liability.124 Defensiveness will not always be abrogated in the same way. De Mot and Faure state that emotional costs can be substantial in certain circumstances—for example, mental health clinicians are generally more willing to shoulder the emotional cost of adverse litigation attendant on defensively declining to release a potentially dangerous patient than they would the emotional cost of releasing a patient who then harms third parties.125 While insurance may mitigate defensive practice in a financial sense, it cannot indemnify emotional, reputational and other nonfinancial costs which may also bring to bear significant chilling effects.126

Gregory is authority for the proposition that where emotional costs are not likely to

flow from litigation, insurance should tend to overwhelm the chilling effect argument.127 McGechan J considered that insurance would defray the financial burden such that defensive practice was not a concern. His judgment is not without flaws. He opined that liability should promote improved performance and more effective administration. If insurance is an equalising agent, as McGechan J holds, it follows that the behavioural effect of liability should be neutral.

This contradiction typifies the confusion in New Zealand law in terms of defensive practice and deterrence concerns. Gregory suggests that liability will not attract defensive behaviour where insurance is available, but it will engender increased deterrence. This is a non sequitur, and undesirable in terms of clarity in the law. It only affirms the impression, previously noted, that liability’s behavioural effect will tend to be framed as either

120 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 126. 121 At 128.

122 At 126.

123 At 126.

124 Poythress and Brodsky, above n 114, at 157.

125 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 132–133. 126 At 129.

127 Gregory, above n 8.

defensiveness or deterrence in light of other prevailing considerations. In future, New Zealand courts should carefully contemplate the behavioural influence that loss-spreading measures are likely to have, and allow defensive practice concerns their proper place in that contemplation.

D The defendant authority

The Law Commission report states that a public authority’s level of legal knowledge, conscientiousness and competence influences its ability to respond to liability appropriately.128 A competent authority should be able to order policies and systems so that responsible administration results. This would be organisation-specific. It would be extremely difficult to definitively circumscribe the distribution of competence within and between different public authority contexts.129

Dissemination of relevant information within an authority’s organisational structure is important. Schwartz stresses that litigation will not deter misconduct if the authority does not have robust information practices.130 If public officers are not informed of potential liability attaching to an act or omission, they are unlikely to modify their conduct. Accordingly, she argues that the provision of information relating to litigation across an authority’s organisational structure should engender positive changes in the deterrent effect of actions for damages.131 Chilling effects may arise from lack of certainty around reasonable standards. Therefore, effective informational structures would help to provide this certainty. This would reduce the potential for defensive practice. John Hartshorne, Nicholas Smith and Rosemarie Everton also argue that the attitude of the authority will impact significantly on whether deterrence or defensiveness results from liability. 132 Employee training, professional development and reinforcement of correct procedure should instil a respectful appreciation of liability, rather than excessive apprehension.

New Zealand courts have tended not to expressly consider questions of public authority knowledge, competence and information structures in liability assessments. They have, however, consistently placed importance on the nature of the authority’s discretion, and the statutory framework in which it operates. A common theme in the case law is that authorities with strong discretionary powers, or which are of a quasi-judicial nature are not normally liable in negligence. Ellis, Fyfe, Morrison, Bella Vista, Monticello, Sacramento and The Grange are all authorities for the proposition that where a given authority has a strong discretion empowered by statute, or is of a quasi-judicial character, defensive practice concerns carry much more weight.133 Conversely, where a common law duty is thought appropriate to buttress statutory duties, deterrence has been stressed.134

128 Law Commission, above n 98, at [B.87]. 129 At [B.82].

130 Joanna C Schwartz “Myths and Mechanics of Deterrence: The Role of Lawsuits in Law Enforcement Decisionmaking” (2010) 57 UCLA L Rev 1023 at 1085.

131 At 1086.

132 John Hartshorne, Nicholas Smith and Rosemarie Everton “‘Caparo Under Fire’: A Study into the Effects upon the Fire Service of Liability in Negligence” (2000) 63 MLR 502 at 520.

133 Ellis, above n 16, at [175]; Fyfe, above n 25, at [58]; Morrison, above n 31, at 338; Bella Vista, above n 36, at [75]; Monticello, above n 44, at [88]; Sacramento, above n 47, at [93]; and The Grange, above n 51, at [53].

134 See Gregory, above n 8, at 230; and Prince, above n 54, at 282.

A related argument is that immunity is justified where the risk of defensive practice by a given authority is thought to have significant negative implications for the public interest.135 Police therefore have been the most obvious beneficiary of immunity from actions in negligence. This reasoning has been evident in New Zealand.136 It is difficult to delimit which authorities should attract a privileged immunity. Justifications for these immunities are ringing hollow—widely criticised in legal commentaries and departed from in other jurisdictions.137 While the New Zealand courts have not followed the House of Lords’ example such that defensive practice operates as a blanket immunity, there nevertheless remains room for a more reasoned approach in assessing liability. By integrating considerations of legal competence and information into existing inquiries into statutory frameworks and discretion, the New Zealand courts will be better placed to make principled assessments about which authorities should be insulated on the basis of defensive practice.

E Quality of conduct and proximity

The kind of wrong committed and harm suffered are relevant considerations in determining whether liability will promote defensiveness or deterrence. The Law Commission notes that “[i]llegality can take a number of forms ... it should not be assumed that they are all equally responsive to a specific mode of deterrence.”138 Liability could incentivise higher standards of care in cases where the authority has been inattentive.139 The same consequence is unlikely where the alleged negligence stems from a lack of resources.140 Where the harmed party has suffered a personal injury, this may give rise to a stronger call for deterrence. In New Zealand, this tends not to be a relevant consideration because of the no-fault accident compensation scheme. 141 Liability would only result where the authority’s conduct was so outrageous that exemplary damages would be warranted. 142 This was evident in Hobson, where William Young P considered that defensive practice concerns were strong, and the accident compensation scheme meant that concerns of appropriate redress were not a counterweight.154

The nature of the claim in relation to the impugned conduct affects the relative strength of defensive practice concerns. Certain types of conduct are scarcely justiciable. Takaro and The Grange suggest that where the exercise of powers can be described as having a policy rather than operational character, a duty should not properly be found.143 Morrison held that a negligence standard was inappropriate in a case of alleged error in interpretation.144 These cases suggest that where questions of justiciability are at issue, defensive practice concerns appear to carry more weight.

135
Hill, above n 1, at 63.
136
Evers, above n 20, at [34].
137
See, for example, Claire McIvor, above n 96, at 133.
138
Law Commission, above n 98, at [B.9].
139
At [B.10].
140
At [B.10].
141
Accident Compensation Act 2001, s 317.
142
Section 319.
154
Hobson, above n 67, at [127].
143
Takaro, above n 86, at 709; and The Grange, above n 51, at [32].
144
Morrison, above n 31, at 338.

Proximity is important. Where the authority is “causally peripheral”, the defensive practice concern offers a compelling reason to deny a finding of duty. 145 This most obviously comes to bear in cases involving an authority’s failure to control a harm-causing third party. This reasoning is evident in the body of New Zealand case law, for example Evers and Hobson.146 In the former case, it was found that a police failure to control did not warrant a duty. The finding of a duty in the case of a positive negligent arrest by police in Fyfe signals that the public authority context is not determinative. This proposition is supported by the international authorities. The United Kingdom Supreme Court, in Robinson v Chief Constable of West Yorkshire Police, 147 belatedly disturbed the longstanding blanket immunity of police conferred by Hill. This case also dealt with a negligent arrest and found police could properly be liable in negligence for positive negligent acts.148 The vital component of Hill warranting insulation from liability was that the police there had failed to protect a victim (an omission).149

In weak-proximity situations—such as where a failure to control or protect has arisen from an omission—joint and several liability operates inequitably. The relative causal responsibility of the authority and the primary tortfeasor is lopsided.150 Jane Stapleton stresses that this problem is particularly acute where the peripheral party is a public authority. Deep-pocketed authorities are sometimes improperly made to pay damages out of budgets that should be applied to public duties.151 Public authorities are tasked with upholding the public interest and should therefore not be exposed to liability out of proportion with their actual responsibility.152 Gendall J, in Monticello, held that this was an important consideration that tended to add weight to concerns of defensive practice.153

The proximity question is a two-way street. Hanna Wilberg has identified that where a close proximate relationship exists, courts have tended to favour deterrence. 154 For example, where there is a discernible assumption of responsibility on the part of the authority, the defensive practice concern has carried little weight.155 Similar reasoning is evident in the New Zealand context—S v Midcentral and Prince both involved close proximity relationships, and in both cases deterrence and high standards of administration were stressed in a finding for duty. 156 Wilberg suggests that defensive practice should not be regarded as a de facto immunity from liability, but a qualified protection that is subject to several factors—with proximity being a key feature in the overriding deterrence/defensiveness calculation.157

145 Jane Stapleton “Duty of care: peripheral parties and alternative opportunities for deterrence” (1995) 111 LQR 301 at 310.

146 Evers, above n 20, at [33]; and Hobson, above n 67, at [180] and [187].

147 Robinson, above n 3. 148 At [55], [73] and [80].

149 Robinson, above n 3, at [53]–[54].

150 Stapleton, above n 145, at 311. 151 At 313.

152 At 314.

153 Monticello, above n 44, at [62].

154 Hanna Wilberg “Defensive practice or conflict of duties? Policy concerns in public authority negligence claims” (2010) 126 LQR 420 at 435.

155 See, for example, Swinney, above n 5.

156 S v Midcentral, above n 12, at [48]; and Prince, above n 54, at 282.

157 Wilberg, above n 154, at 437.

F Conflict of duties

The formulation of the defensive practice concern affects its strength. Defensive practice can manifest as a conflict of duties.158 As stated earlier, where an alleged duty of care is incompatible with the strong existing public duty of a given authority, this provides sufficient reason to decline to impose that alleged duty. Wilberg explains that a conflicting duties situation necessarily entails a form of defensive practice. Where a statutory scheme treats one competing interest as paramount, any duty that would conflict with that interest directly interferes with the public authority’s ability to perform its primary function. 159 Wilberg argues that defensive practice is more readily defensible in terms of “authority and ... inherent persuasiveness” where it is formulated as a strong conflict of duties argument.160

Strong conflict of duties situations often arise as an incompatibility between the interests of plaintiff suspects and victims, the latter of which certain authorities have public duties to protect.161 Wilberg says that a conflicting duties argument may also arise even where the plaintiff is a victim. This may be so if the relevant public duty is not limited to victim protection, and cannot require protection of all potential victims at all times (that is, an individual duty conflicting with a broader duty owed to the public generally).162 Perhaps broadly similar reasoning can be attributed to William Young P in Hobson. 163 He considered that proposed duties to supervise or warn would be inconsistent with the public interest in parolee reintegration, and the corresponding duties imposed by the governing legislation. As Wilberg argues, however, this formulation of the doctrine is less persuasive. 164 Indeed, in Couch Elias CJ attacked this approach as conferring an unjustifiable blanket immunity that may be based on erroneous assumptions.165 It seems fair to conclude that, to date, the weaker conflicting duties argument has not been effective in negating liability in the New Zealand context.

Conflict of duties is invoked frequently in the context of child protection. Courts have tended to find that no duty is owed to a parent suspected of abuse, as that duty would clash with the public duty of social workers to uphold the interests of possible victim children. This principle has been seen in operation in the United Kingdom, Australia and Canada.166 In New Zealand, B v Attorney-General is an authority for the strong conflicting duties formulation of defensive practice acting to negate liability.167

There are other public authority contexts in which a conflict of duties situation could operate to dispose of liability. Wilberg argues that cases like Elguzouli-Daf v Commissioner

158 Cherie Booth and Daniel Squires The Negligence Liability of Public Authorities (Oxford University Press, New York, 2006); and Wilberg, above n 154.

159 Wilberg, above n 154, at 424. 160 At 422.

161 At 425.

162 At 425, in reference to Cooper v Hobart [2001] 3 SCR 537 at [44]–[50].

163 Hobson, above n 67, at [125].

164 Wilberg, above n 154, at 425.

165 Couch, above n 78, at [36].

166 See, for example, JD v East Berkshire Community Health NHS Trust [2005] UKHL 23, [2005] 2 AC 373 at [85]–[89], [113]–[114] and [126]–[132]; A v Essex County Council [2003] EWCA Civ 1848, [2004] 1 WLR 1881; Sullivan v Moody [2001] HCA 59, (2001) 207 CLR 562 at [60]–[62]; and Syl Apps Secure Treatment Centre v BD [2007] SCC 38, [2007] 3 SCR 83 at [41]–[50].

167 B v Attorney-General, above n 62, at [30].

of Police of the Metropolis and Brooks v Commissioner of Police for the Metropolis,168 which were dismissed on the basis of defensive practice generally, could be better justified on the basis of a strong conflict of duties.169 These cases concerned the functions of the Crown Prosecution Service and the police force respectively, and applied the core principle of Hill in a straightforward manner. However, given that prosecutors and police are under a public duty to protect victims, and that these cases involved proposed duties to potential suspects, the principle of conflicting duties should come into play.170

The conflicting duties argument has been countenanced by Australian courts. 171 Equally, however, the conflicting duties doctrine in the police context has been dismissed in Canada.172 The majority in Hill v Hamilton-Wentworth Regional Police Services Board held that a duty of care to suspects would not place police officers under incompatible obligations.173 There was a greater interest in the avoidance of wrongful convictions, and the suspect (as a member of the public) shared in the greater public interest of diligent investigation.174 McLachlin CJ considered that a duty would have positive implications in terms of responsible administration, in the same breath dismissing the possibility that chilling effects could arise.175 Chilling effects were speculative and tort liability would have no adverse effect on police capacity to investigate.176 Her approach to the conflict question is similar to the dismissive attitude adopted by Lord Bingham in his dissenting judgment in JD v East Berkshire Community Health NHS Trust.177

With respect to the Chief Justice, it is difficult to escape the sense that she has fallen into the same kind of loose reasoning that she criticises. It is unclear why she would readily dismiss concerns of defensive practice as conjectural, while at the same time asserting that increased prudence, higher standards and more effective administration would result from liability. Such arguments are equally subject to the empirical question. It is possible that McLachlin CJ’s personal convictions regarding corrective justice coloured her reasoning, and that her judgment was massaged to achieve a desired outcome. Charron J’s minority judgment represents a more sensible application of principle. She rightly identifies that a suspected criminal’s interest in being left unmolested by police will always be in conflict with the wider public interest in crime investigation.178 She concludes, therefore, that a private duty of care should not be recognised to a suspect under investigation.179

Insofar as the responsible administration argument is relevant in finding a duty, a strong conflict of duties argument would usually negate it. While a general defensive practice concern is subject to the ambiguity of a deterrence/defensiveness calculation, the strong conflict of duties situation poses an unambiguously negative threat. 180 Wilberg further argues that a strong conflict of duties effectively negates the empirical question in

168
Elguzouli-Daf, above n 4; and Brooks v Commissioner of Police for the Metropolis [2005] UKHL

169
Wilberg, above n 154, at 429 and 445.
170
At 429.
171
Tame v New South Wales [2002] HCA 35, (2002) 211 CLR 317 at [231].
172
Hill v Hamilton-Wentworth Regional Police Services Board [2007] SCC 41, [2007] 3 SCR 129.
173
At [40] per McLachlin CJ.
174
At [41].
175
At [43].
176
At [57].
177
JD v East Berkshire, above n 182.
178
Hill, above n 172, at [140].
179
At [153].
180
Wilberg, above n 154, at 438.

that where there is any possibility of bringing about such a strongly negative consequence, there is a large incentive not to take the risk.181 McLachlin CJ’s points in favour of liability where police are subject to conflicting duties therefore erode.

It is important that the legislative intent of Parliament is not undercut by the courts, and this rationale provides additional support to a conflict of duties argument where the overriding public duty is one conferred by statute.182 Accordingly, the strong conflict of duties situation provides a relatively unimpeachable argument against finding a duty of care. Where it can be properly identified, this should in most cases be sufficient to override public interest in deterrence. Furthermore, the courts should be cautious of invoking the relatively weaker general formulation in situations where examination would reveal the conflicting duties argument to be appropriate. Presumably, there will be a range of circumstances that would constitute a conflict of duties warranting protection from liability. In New Zealand, increased judicial scrutiny and recognition of the different forms of defensive practice should provide clarity in explaining why certain public authority contexts should attract protection more than others.183

G Alternatives

It is worth considering to what extent certain objectives of tort law, such as deterrence and responsible administration, may be achieved by alternative means. Public authorities may be deterred from improper conduct through internal procedures, negative media exposure, and judicial review. De Mot and Faure similarly argue that tangential consequences of liability can strongly incentivise either deterrence or defensive behaviour.184 The reputational loss following from an adverse verdict can have chilling effects where the media frames the authority’s conduct in an unflattering light. 185 The extent of this will again depend on the particular nature of the defendant authority. For example, Simon Halliday, Jonathan Ilan and Colin Scott state that sectors like social work, education and policing would tend to attract greater political costs than would an authority responsible for upkeep of roads.186

An authority usually has relationships with the public, other authorities, and regulators.187 Liability will influence the relative esteem the authority is held in by these parties. The strength of the influence will depend on several factors bearing upon these relationships—such as whether the authority’s conduct is politically damaging or expedient, whether claims are responded to quickly and satisfactorily, whether claims are settled out of court or litigated in the public domain, and whether the performance indicators in relation to liability set by regulators are respected by the authority.188

As reputational pressures can arguably chill the public authority’s behaviour, accountability pressures beyond liability can also promote responsible administration.189

181 At 438.

182 Wilberg, above 154, at 439; and Booth and Squires, above n 158, at [4.05].

183 Wilberg, above n 154, at 446.

184 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 123. 185 At 127.

186 Simon Halliday, Jonathan Ilan and Colin Scott “The Public Management of Liability Risks” (2011) 31 OJLS 527 at 548.

187 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 128.

188 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 128. 189 At 128.

Halliday, Ilan and Scott argue this point in terms of “bottom-up pressures” acting upon the authority, such as complaints processes, and “top-down pressures” such as performance audits and reviews.190 They argue that accountability regimes outside the usual resort to tort measures can in this way “weaken the grip of liability risks on public service delivery”.191 Laura CH Hoyano, conversely, casts internal inquiries in an uncertain light in the wake of Brooks.192 She argues that the inquiry into the murder of Stephen Lawrence proved that post-mortem examinations may be subject to deficiencies, and that the disciplinary processes undertaken by authorities may lack independence. 193 That her argument is situated specifically in the context of police is an important qualification. These concerns may not necessarily come to bear as strongly in other public authority contexts. This should be a determination for the courts, assuming they are in possession of adequate information about the relevant authority’s internal systems and procedures. New Zealand case law is divided on the suitability of alternative means of accountability and deterrence. In Prince, Henry J noted that accountability could not be satisfactorily achieved through other means like making a complaint to the Ombudsman, ministerial and parliamentary oversight, or judicial review.194 Moreover, in S v Midcentral, William Young J considered that disciplinary proceedings for psychiatric staff who “negligently” released dangerous patients would be far more likely to promote unnecessarily defensive medicine than the possibility that their employers face a claim for exemplary damages.195 However, Ellis, Bella Vista, and Morrison made clear that measures like complaints processes and causes of action against other parties could be persuasive

in New Zealand.196

It is not clear what particular features of the cases made alternatives to tortious liability more compelling in some contexts than others. This is typical of confused and internally inconsistent jurisprudence on defensive practice and deterrence concerns as they relate to public authorities. New Zealand courts can shore up these deficiencies in future cases by expressly contemplating the appropriateness of monetary liability with respect to likely reputational costs of litigation, availability of valid alternatives, and the scope of political accountability in a given public authority context. These factors all bear directly on the strength of the defensive practice concern and are underrepresented in the body of New Zealand law.

IV Conclusion

Are defensive practice arguments defensible? How significant is the public interest in deterring an authority’s wrongful conduct? What should the approach to negligence liability be in New Zealand in light of the competing considerations of chilling effects and improved administration? These are hefty questions, to which there are no clear-cut answers. Each consideration in the overall calculation seems to have a countervailing

190 Halliday, Ilan and Scott, above n 186, at 548. 191 At 540.

192 Brooks, above n 168.

193 Laura CH Hoyano “Policing Flawed Police Investigations: Unravelling the Blanket” (1999) 62 MLR 912 at 934.

194 Prince, above n 54, at 289.

195 S v Midcentral, above n 12, at [47].

196 Ellis, above n 16, at [171]; Bella Vista, above n 36, at [60]; and Morrison, above n 31, at 338.

argument, making any definitive approach to policy tenuous. Any arguments about the appropriate ambit of the defensive practice concern must be subject to the qualification that a single, unified formula is likely impossible.197

My aim has not been to propose an absolute solution. Rather, I have sought to show the most universal variables bearing upon the strength and validity of the concern in different public authority contexts. This forms a useful heuristic for calculating whether liability is appropriate in a given situation. I have used these variables to both explain and criticise the existing body of New Zealand law dealing with defensive practice and deterrence concerns. I have also shown how some of these important factors are comparatively underdeveloped and unrepresented in existing jurisprudence. I have suggested that deliberate and express contemplation of these neglected factors should allow for a more reasoned approach to weighing defensive practice against deterrence in the wider liability equation.

The charge may be levelled that a broad, multifactorial framework could have the effect of making the liability equation even more fragmented and needlessly complex. I answer that some kind of taxonomy must surely be better than the confused assortment of authorities that currently passes for jurisprudence on defensive practice and deterrence. Furthermore, this proposed system is to be regarded as a gestalt rather than a definitive checklist. The overall calculation will be highly context-sensitive. As Halliday, Ilan and Scott observe, a number of factors must be considered when “thinking, context by context, about the promise or threat of tort law”.198 It is impossible to quantify the relative weight of each of these factors in the duty equation. This would be a determination for the courts in light of the particular circumstances.

It is clear that there is still much to be established about the way in which public authorities modify behaviour in response to competing incentives and disincentives (financial, reputational, political or otherwise). Bare assertions about the influence of legal challenge and monetary penalties on decision making must therefore be made cautiously.199 On balance, however, it is fair to state that reliance on defensive practice as a wholesale exclusionary rule for liability is untenable.200 This does little justice to the nuances involved in the wider duty inquiry. Equally, broad brush statements asserting the desirability of deterrence and responsible administration are often plagued by a seemingly wilful blindness toward the legitimate rationales underlying the defensive practice concern.

The body of authority considering defensiveness and deterrence in the policy arm of the duty question has left the law in a rather confused state. This must be the kind of unsatisfactory state of affairs that Burrough J contemplated when he characterised public policy as “a very unruly horse ... once you get astride it you never know where it will carry you”.201 However, attention to the factors identified in this article should ameliorate this concern. As De Mot and Faure conclude, due contemplation of the relevant factors will help to “[delineate] the types of cases in which a restrictive approach is justifiable ... [this]

197 Mandy Shircore “Police Liability for Negligent Investigations: When Will a Duty of Care Arise?” [2006] DeakinLawRw 2; (2006) 11 Deakin LR 33 at 62.

198 Halliday, Ilan and Scott, above n 186, at 549.

199 Law Commission, above n 98, at [B.54].

200 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 133.

201 Richardson v Mellish [1824] EngR 715; (1824) 2 Bing 229 at [252].

could significantly limit the scope for the chilling effect argument to be incorrectly decided”.202 Ultimately, while the duty calculation will inevitably be subject to a complex range of difficulties and considerations, this is no reason to shy away from attempting to tame the policy horse. The continued search for clarity in tort law is one from which we should not be deterred.

202 De Mot and Faure, above n 104, at 133.


NZLII: Copyright Policy | Disclaimers | Privacy Policy | Feedback
URL: http://www.nzlii.org/nz/journals/NZPubIntLawJl/2018/9.html